Term logic revived in medieval times, first in Islamic logic by Alpharabius in the tenth century, and later in Christian Europe in the twelfth century with the advent of new logic, remaining dominant until the advent of predicate logic in the late nineteenth century.
However, even if eclipsed by newer logical systems, term logic still plays a significant role in the study of logic. Rather than radically breaking with term logic, modern logics typically expand it.
Aristotle's system
Aristotle's logical work is collected in the six texts that are collectively known as the Organon. Two of these texts in particular, namely the Prior Analytics and De Interpretatione, contain the heart of Aristotle's treatment of judgements and formal inference, and it is principally this part of Aristotle's works that is about term logic. Modern work on Aristotle's logic builds on the tradition started in 1951 with the establishment by Jan Lukasiewicz of a revolutionary paradigm.[1] Lukasiewicz's approach was reinvigorated in the early 1970s by John Corcoran and Timothy Smiley – which informs modern translations of Prior Analytics by Robin Smith in 1989 and Gisela Striker in 2009.[2]
The Prior Analytics represents the first formal study of logic, where logic is understood as the study of arguments. An argument is a series of true or false statements which lead to a true or false conclusion.[3] In the Prior Analytics, Aristotle identifies valid and invalid forms of arguments called syllogisms. A syllogism is an argument that consists of at least three sentences: at least two premises and a conclusion. Although Aristotle does not call them "categorical sentences", tradition does; he deals with them briefly in the Analytics and more extensively in On Interpretation.[4] Each proposition (statement that is a thought of the kind expressible by a declarative sentence)[5] of a syllogism is a categorical sentence which has a subject and a predicate connected by a verb. The usual way of connecting the subject and predicate of a categorical sentence as Aristotle does in On Interpretation is by using a linking verb e.g. P is S. However, in the Prior Analytics Aristotle rejects the usual form in favour of three of his inventions:
P belongs to S
P is predicated of S
P is said of S
Aristotle does not explain why he introduces these innovative expressions but scholars conjecture that the reason may have been that it facilitates the use of letters instead of terms avoiding the ambiguity that results in Greek when letters are used with the linking verb.[6] In his formulation of syllogistic propositions, instead of the copula ("All/some... are/are not..."), Aristotle uses the expression, "... belongs to/does not belong to all/some..." or "... is said/is not said of all/some..."[7] There are four different types of categorical sentences: universal affirmative (A), universal negative (E), particular affirmative (I) and particular negative (O).
A - A belongs to every B
E - A belongs to no B
I - A belongs to some B
O - A does not belong to some B
A method of symbolization that originated and was used in the Middle Ages greatly simplifies the study of the Prior Analytics.
Following this tradition then, let:
a = belongs to every
e = belongs to no
i = belongs to some
o = does not belong to some
Categorical sentences may then be abbreviated as follows:
AaB = A belongs to every B (Every B is A)
AeB = A belongs to no B (No B is A)
AiB = A belongs to some B (Some B is A)
AoB = A does not belong to some B (Some B is not A)
From the viewpoint of modern logic, only a few types of sentences can be represented in this way.[8]
Basics
The fundamental assumption behind the theory is that the formal model of propositions are composed of two logical symbols called terms – hence the name "two-term theory" or "term logic" – and that the reasoning process is in turn built from propositions:
The term is a part of speech representing something, but which is not true or false in its own right, such as "man" or "mortal". As originally conceived, all terms would be drawn from one of ten categories enumerated by Aristotle in his Organon, classifying all objects and qualities within the domain of logical discourse.
The formal model of proposition consists of two terms, one of which, the "predicate", is "affirmed" or "denied" of the other, the "subject", and which is capable of truth or falsity.
A proposition may be universal or particular, and it may be affirmative or negative. Traditionally, the four kinds of propositions are:
A-type: Universal and affirmative ("All philosophers are mortal")
E-type: Universal and negative ("All philosophers are not mortal")
I-type: Particular and affirmative ("Some philosophers are mortal")
O-type: Particular and negative ("Some philosophers are not mortal")
This was called the fourfold scheme of propositions (see types of syllogism for an explanation of the letters A, I, E, and O in the traditional square). Aristotle's originalsquare of opposition, however, does not lack existential import.
Term
A term (Greek ὅρος horos) is the basic component of the proposition. The original meaning of the horos (and also of the Latin terminus) is "extreme" or "boundary". The two terms lie on the outside of the proposition, joined by the act of affirmation or denial.
For early modern logicians like Arnauld (whose Port-Royal Logic was the best-known text of his day), it is a psychological entity like an "idea" or "concept". Mill considers it a word. To assert "all Greeks are men" is not to say that the concept of Greeks is the concept of men, or that word "Greeks" is the word "men". A proposition cannot be built from real things or ideas, but it is not just meaningless words either.
Proposition
In term logic, a "proposition" is simply a form of language: a particular kind of sentence, in which the subject and predicate are combined, so as to assert something true or false. It is not a thought, or an abstract entity. The word "propositio" is from the Latin, meaning the first premise of a syllogism. Aristotle uses the word premise (protasis) as a sentence affirming or denying one thing or another (Posterior Analytics 1. 1 24a 16), so a premise is also a form of words.
However, as in modern philosophical logic, it means that which is asserted by the sentence. Writers before Frege and Russell, such as Bradley, sometimes spoke of the "judgment" as something distinct from a sentence, but this is not quite the same. As a further confusion the word "sentence" derives from the Latin, meaning an opinion or judgment, and so is equivalent to "proposition".
The logical quality of a proposition is whether it is affirmative (the predicate is affirmed of the subject) or negative (the predicate is denied of the subject). Thus every philosopher is mortal is affirmative, since the mortality of philosophers is affirmed universally, whereas no philosopher is mortal is negative by denying such mortality in particular.
The quantity of a proposition is whether it is universal (the predicate is affirmed or denied of all subjects or of "the whole") or particular (the predicate is affirmed or denied of some subject or a "part" thereof). In case where existential import is assumed, quantification implies the existence of at least one subject, unless disclaimed.
Singular terms
For Aristotle, the distinction between singular[citation needed] and universal is a fundamental metaphysical one, and not merely grammatical. A singular term for Aristotle is primary substance, which can only be predicated of itself: (this) "Callias" or (this) "Socrates" are not predicable of any other thing, thus one does not say every Socrates one says every human (De Int. 7; Meta. D9, 1018a4). It may feature as a grammatical predicate, as in the sentence "the person coming this way is Callias". But it is still a logical subject.
He contrasts universal (katholou)[9] secondary substance, genera, with primary substance, particular (kath' hekaston)[9][10] specimens. The formal nature of universals, in so far as they can be generalized "always, or for the most part", is the subject matter of both scientific study and formal logic.[11]
The essential feature of the syllogism is that, of the four terms in the two premises, one must occur twice. Thus
All Greeks are men
All men are mortal.
The subject of one premise, must be the predicate of the other, and so it is necessary to eliminate from the logic any terms which cannot function both as subject and predicate, namely singular terms.
However, in a popular 17th-century version of the syllogism, Port-Royal Logic, singular terms were treated as universals:[12]
All men are mortals
All Socrates are men
All Socrates are mortals
This is clearly awkward, a weakness exploited by Frege in his devastating attack on the system.
The famous syllogism "Socrates is a man ...", is frequently quoted as though from Aristotle,[13] but in fact, it is nowhere in the Organon. Sextus Empiricus in his Hyp. Pyrrh (Outlines of Pyrronism) ii. 164 first mentions the related syllogism "Socrates is a human being, Every human being is an animal, Therefore, Socrates is an animal."
The three figures
Depending on the position of the middle term, Aristotle divides the syllogism into three kinds: syllogism in the first, second, and third figure.[14] If the Middle Term is subject of one premise and predicate of the other, the premises are in the First Figure. If the Middle Term is predicate of both premises, the premises are in the Second Figure. If the Middle Term is subject of both premises, the premises are in the Third Figure.[15]
Symbolically, the Three Figures may be represented as follows:[16]
First figure
Second figure
Third figure
Predicate — Subject
Predicate — Subject
Predicate — Subject
Major premise
A ------------ B
B ------------ A
A ------------ B
Minor premise
B ------------ C
B ------------ C
C ------------ B
Conclusion
A ********** C
A ********** C
A ********** C
The fourth figure
In Aristotelian syllogistic (Prior Analytics, Bk I Caps 4-7), syllogisms are divided into three figures according to the position of the middle term in the two premises. The fourth figure, in which the middle term is the predicate in the major premise and the subject in the minor, was added by Aristotle's pupil Theophrastus and does not occur in Aristotle's work, although there is evidence that Aristotle knew of fourth-figure syllogisms.[17]
Syllogism in the first figure
In the Prior Analytics translated by A. J. Jenkins as it appears in volume 8 of the Great Books of the Western World, Aristotle says of the First Figure: "... If A is predicated of all B, and B of all C, A must be predicated of all C."[18] In the Prior Analytics translated by Robin Smith, Aristotle says of the first figure: "... For if A is predicated of every B and B of every C, it is necessary for A to be predicated of every C."[19]
Taking a = is predicated of all = is predicated of every, and using the symbolical method used in the Middle Ages, then the first figure is simplified to:[20]
If AaB
and BaC
then AaC.
Or what amounts to the same thing:
AaB, BaC; therefore AaC
When the four syllogistic propositions, a, e, i, o are placed in the first figure, Aristotle comes up with the following valid forms of deduction for the first figure:
AaB, BaC; therefore, AaC
AeB, BaC; therefore, AeC
AaB, BiC; therefore, AiC
AeB, BiC; therefore, AoC
In the Middle Ages, for mnemonic reasons they were called "Barbara", "Celarent", "Darii" and "Ferio" respectively.[21]
The difference between the first figure and the other two figures is that the syllogism of the first figure is complete while that of the second and third is not. This is important in Aristotle's theory of the syllogism for the first figure is axiomatic while the second and third require proof. The proof of the second and third figure always leads back to the first figure.[22]
Syllogism in the second figure
This is what Robin Smith says in English that Aristotle said in Ancient Greek: "... If M belongs to every N but to no X, then neither will N belong to any X. For if M belongs to no X, neither does X belong to any M; but M belonged to every N; therefore, X will belong to no N (for the first figure has again come about)."[23]
The above statement can be simplified by using the symbolical method used in the Middle Ages:
If MaN
but MeX
then NeX.
For if MeX
then XeM
but MaN
therefore XeN.
When the four syllogistic propositions, a, e, i, o are placed in the second figure, Aristotle comes up with the following valid forms of deduction for the second figure:
MaN, MeX; therefore NeX
MeN, MaX; therefore NeX
MeN, MiX; therefore NoX
MaN, MoX; therefore NoX
In the Middle Ages, for mnemonic reasons they were called respectively "Camestres", "Cesare", "Festino" and "Baroco".[24]
Syllogism in the third figure
Aristotle says in the Prior Analytics, "... If one term belongs to all and another to none of the same thing, or if they both belong to all or none of it, I call such figure the third." Referring to universal terms, "... then when both P and R belongs to every S, it results of necessity that P will belong to some R."[25]
Simplifying:
If PaS
and RaS
then PiR.
When the four syllogistic propositions, a, e, i, o are placed in the third figure, Aristotle develops six more valid forms of deduction:
PaS, RaS; therefore PiR
PeS, RaS; therefore PoR
PiS, RaS; therefore PiR
PaS, RiS; therefore PiR
PoS, RaS; therefore PoR
PeS, RiS; therefore PoR
In the Middle Ages, for mnemonic reasons, these six forms were called respectively: "Darapti", "Felapton", "Disamis", "Datisi", "Bocardo" and "Ferison".[26]
Term logic began to decline in Europe during the Renaissance, when logicians like Rodolphus Agricola Phrisius (1444–1485) and Ramus (1515–1572) began to promote place logics. The logical tradition called Port-Royal Logic, or sometimes "traditional logic", saw propositions as combinations of ideas rather than of terms, but otherwise followed many of the conventions of term logic. It remained influential, especially in England, until the 19th century. Leibniz created a distinctive logical calculus, but nearly all of his work on logic remained unpublished and unremarked until Louis Couturat went through the Leibniz Nachlass around 1900, publishing his pioneering studies in logic.
19th-century attempts to algebraize logic, such as the work of Boole (1815–1864) and Venn (1834–1923), typically yielded systems highly influenced by the term-logic tradition. The first predicate logic was that of Frege's landmark Begriffsschrift (1879), little read before 1950, in part because of its eccentric notation. Modern predicate logic as we know it began in the 1880s with the writings of Charles Sanders Peirce, who influenced Peano (1858–1932) and even more, Ernst Schröder (1841–1902). It reached fruition in the hands of Bertrand Russell and A. N. Whitehead, whose Principia Mathematica (1910–13) made use of a variant of Peano's predicate logic.
Term logic also survived to some extent in traditional Roman Catholic education, especially in seminaries. Medieval Catholic theology, especially the writings of Thomas Aquinas, had a powerfully Aristotelean cast, and thus term logic became a part of Catholic theological reasoning. For example, Joyce's Principles of Logic (1908; 3rd edition 1949), written for use in Catholic seminaries, made no mention of Frege or of Bertrand Russell.[28][page needed][need quotation to verify]
Revival
Some philosophers have complained that predicate logic:
Suffers from theoretical problems, probably the most serious being empty names and identity statements.
Even academic philosophers entirely in the mainstream, such as Gareth Evans, have written as follows:
"I come to semantic investigations with a preference for homophonic theories; theories which try to take serious account of the syntactic and semantic devices which actually exist in the language ...I would prefer [such] a theory ... over a theory which is only able to deal with [sentences of the form "all A's are B's"] by "discovering" hidden logical constants ... The objection would not be that such [Fregean] truth conditions are not correct, but that, in a sense which we would all dearly love to have more exactly explained, the syntactic shape of the sentence is treated as so much misleading surface structure" (Evans 1977)
Boole’s acceptance of Aristotle
George Boole's unwavering acceptance of Aristotle's logic is emphasized by the historian of logic John Corcoran in an accessible introduction to Laws of Thought[29] Corcoran also wrote a point-by-point comparison of Prior Analytics and Laws of Thought.[30] According to Corcoran, Boole fully accepted and endorsed Aristotle's logic. Boole's goals were “to go under, over, and beyond” Aristotle's logic by:
providing it with mathematical foundations involving equations;
extending the class of problems it could treat– from assessing validity to solving equations; and
expanding the range of applications it could handle– e.g. from propositions having only two terms to those having arbitrarily many.
More specifically, Boole agreed with what Aristotle said; Boole's ‘disagreements’, if they might be called that, concern what Aristotle did not say. First, in the realm of foundations, Boole reduced the four propositional forms of Aristotle's logic to formulas in the form of equations– by itself a revolutionary idea. Second, in the realm of logic's problems, Boole's addition of equation solving to logic– another revolutionary idea –involved Boole's doctrine that Aristotle's rules of inference (the “perfect syllogisms”) must be supplemented by rules for equation solving. Third, in the realm of applications, Boole's system could handle multi-term propositions and arguments whereas Aristotle could handle only two-termed subject-predicate propositions and arguments. For example, Aristotle's system could not deduce “No quadrangle that is a square is a rectangle that is a rhombus” from “No square that is a quadrangle is a rhombus that is a rectangle” or from “No rhombus that is a rectangle is a square that is a quadrangle”.
^Degnan, M. 1994. Recent Work in Aristotle's Logic. Philosophical Books 35.2 (April, 1994): 81-89.
^*Review of "Aristotle, Prior Analytics: Book I, Gisela Striker (translation and commentary), Oxford UP, 2009, 268pp., $39.95 (pbk), ISBN978-0-19-925041-7." in the Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews, 2010.02.02.
^Nolt, John; Rohatyn, Dennis (1988). Logic: Schaum's outline of theory and problems. McGraw Hill. p. 1. ISBN0-07-053628-7.
^Robin Smith. Aristotle: Prior Analytics. p. XVII.
^John Nolt/Dennis Rohatyn. Logic: Schaum's Outline of Theory and Problems. pp. 274–275.
^Anagnostopoulos, Georgios (2009). A Companion to Aristotle. Wiley-Blackwell. p. 33. ISBN978-1-4051-2223-8.
^Patzig, Günther (1969). Aristotle's theory of the syllogism. Springer. p. 49. ISBN978-90-277-0030-8.
^They are mentioned briefly in the De Interpretatione. Afterwards, in the chapters of the Prior Analytics where Aristotle methodically sets out his theory of the syllogism, they are entirely ignored.
^Arnauld, Antoine and Nicole, Pierre; (1662) La logique, ou l'art de penser. Part 2, chapter 3
^For example: Kapp, Greek Foundations of Traditional Logic, New York 1942, p. 17, Copleston A History of Philosophy Vol. I., p. 277, Russell, A History of Western Philosophy London 1946 p. 218.
^The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle. p. 35. At the foundation of Aristotle's syllogistic is a theory of a specific class of arguments: arguments having as premises exactly two categorical sentences with one term in common.
^Robin Smith. Aristotle: Prior Analytics. p. XVIII.
^Henrik Legerlund. Modal Syllogistics in the Middle Ages. p. 4.
^George Boole. 1854/2003. The Laws of Thought, facsimile of 1854 edition, with an introduction by J. Corcoran. Buffalo: Prometheus Books (2003). Reviewed by James van Evra in Philosophy in Review.24 (2004) 167–169.
^John Corcoran, Aristotle's Prior Analytics and Boole's Laws of Thought, History and Philosophy of Logic, vol. 24 (2003), pp. 261–288.
References
Bochenski, I. M., 1951. Ancient Formal Logic. North-Holland.
Louis Couturat, 1961 (1901). La Logique de Leibniz. Hildesheim: Georg Olms Verlagsbuchhandlung.
Gareth Evans, 1977, "Pronouns, Quantifiers and Relative Clauses," Canadian Journal of Philosophy.
Peter Geach, 1976. Reason and Argument. University of California Press.
Hammond and Scullard, 1992. The Oxford Classical Dictionary. Oxford University Press, ISBN0-19-869117-3.
Joyce, George Hayward, 1949 (1908). Principles of Logic, 3rd ed. Longmans. A manual written for use in Catholic seminaries. Authoritative on traditional logic, with many references to medieval and ancient sources. Contains no hint of modern formal logic. The author lived 1864–1943.
Jan Łukasiewicz, 1951. Aristotle's Syllogistic, from the Standpoint of Modern Formal Logic. Oxford Univ. Press.
William Calvert Kneale and Martha Kneale, 1962. The Development of Logic. Oxford [England] Clarendon Press. Reviews Aristotelean logic and its influences up to modern times.
Miss Universe 1967Sylvia Hitchcock, Miss Universe 1967Tanggal15 Juli 1967TempatMiami Beach Auditorium, Miami Beach, Florida, Amerika SerikatPembawa acaraBob BarkerPenyiaranCBSPeserta56Finalis/Semifinalis15DebutBonaireTidak tampilCeylonEkuadorGuyanaJamaikaLebanonMarokoSurinameThailandTrinidad dan TobagoTampil kembaliHong KongKep. Virgin ASMeksikoRepublik DominikaUruguayPemenangSylvia Hitchcock Amerika SerikatPersahabatanLena MacGarvie SkotlandiaKostum Nasional...
غينادي غوساروف معلومات شخصية الميلاد 11 مارس 1937(1937-03-11)موسكو الوفاة 2 يونيو 2014 (77 سنة)موسكو الطول 1.74 م (5 قدم 8 1⁄2 بوصة) مركز اللعب مهاجم، ولاعب وسط الجنسية الاتحاد السوفيتي روسيا المدرسة الأم معهد موسكو للطيران مسيرة الشباب سنوات فريق سيسكا موسكو FShM M...
Czech Greco-Roman wrestler (born 1988) Artur OmarovArtur Omarov at the 2021 World Wrestling Championships in Oslo, NorwayPersonal informationBorn (1988-08-13) 13 August 1988 (age 35)Dagestan, Soviet Union[1][2]SportCountryCzech RepublicSportAmateur wrestlingWeight class97 kgEventGreco-Roman Medal record Men's Greco-Roman wrestling Representing Czech Republic World Championships 2023 Serbia 97 kg Individual World Cup 2020 Belgrade 97 kg European Championships 20...
Cristhian Stuani Stuani bermain untuk Uruguay di Piala Dunia FIFA 2018Informasi pribadiNama lengkap Cristhian Ricardo Stuani Curbelo[1]Tanggal lahir 12 Oktober 1986 (umur 37)Tempat lahir Tala, UruguayTinggi 186 m (610 ft 3 in)[1]Posisi bermain PenyerangInformasi klubKlub saat ini GironaNomor 7Karier senior*Tahun Tim Tampil (Gol)2004–2007 Danubio 36 (23)2006–2007 → Bella Vista (pinjam) 14 (12)2008–2012 Reggina 18 (1)2009–2010 → Albacete (pinjam)...
Coupe du monde de football 2002 Généralités Sport Football Organisateur(s) FIFA Éditions 17e Lieu(x) Corée du Sud Japon Date 31 mai 2002au 30 juin 2002 Participants 32 (198 partants) Épreuves 64 rencontres Affluence 2 705 197 (moy : 42 268)[1] Site web officiel FIFA Palmarès Tenant du titre France (1) Vainqueur Brésil (5) Finaliste Allemagne Troisième Turquie Buts 161 (moy : 2,51)[1] Meilleur joueur Oliver Kahn Meilleur(s) buteur(s) Ronaldo (8 buts) Navigati...
Ongoing COVID-19 viral pandemic in Mayotte, France COVID-19 pandemic in MayotteDiseaseCOVID-19Virus strainSARS-CoV-2LocationMayotteFirst outbreakWuhan, Hubei, China via FranceArrival date13 March 2020(4 years and 4 weeks)Confirmed cases42,004[1]Recovered41,816[1]Deaths188[1]Government websitemayotte.gouv.fr The ongoing COVID-19 pandemic was confirmed to have reached the French overseas department and region of Mayotte on 10 March 2020. On 31 March, the first ...
ХристианствоБиблия Ветхий Завет Новый Завет Евангелие Десять заповедей Нагорная проповедь Апокрифы Бог, Троица Бог Отец Иисус Христос Святой Дух История христианства Апостолы Хронология христианства Раннее христианство Гностическое христианство Вселенские соборы Н...
Stagno di KosezeStato Slovenia Regione statisticaSlovenia centrale ComuneLubiana Coordinate46°04′02.35″N 14°28′07.76″E / 46.067319°N 14.468822°E46.067319; 14.468822Coordinate: 46°04′02.35″N 14°28′07.76″E / 46.067319°N 14.468822°E46.067319; 14.468822 DimensioniProfondità massima3 m Profondità media2.5 m IdrografiaImmissari principalitorrente Mostec Stagno di Koseze Modifica dati su Wikidata · Manuale Lo stagno di Koseze&...
Министерство природных ресурсов и экологии Российской Федерациисокращённо: Минприроды России Общая информация Страна Россия Юрисдикция Россия Дата создания 12 мая 2008 Предшественники Министерство природных ресурсов Российской Федерации (1996—1998)Министерство охраны...
Roman Catholic diocese in Mexico Diocese of AtlacomulcoDioecesis AtlacomulcanaDiócesis de AtlacomulcoLocationCountry MexicoEcclesiastical provinceProvince of TolucaMetropolitanAtlacomulcoStatisticsArea2,071 sq mi (5,360 km2)Population- Total- Catholics(as of 2006)878,061865,404 (98.6%)Parishes64InformationDenominationRoman CatholicRiteRoman RiteEstablished3 November 1984 (39 years ago)CathedralCathedral of the Divine ProvidenceCurrent leadershipPopeFrancisB...
v · mDélégation de Pennsylvanie au Congrès des États-Unis Sénateurs John Fetterman (D) Bob Casey, Jr. (D) Représentants (liste des districts) Brian Fitzpatrick (R) Brendan Boyle (D) Dwight Evans (D) Madeleine Dean (D) Mary Scanlon (D) Chrissy Houlahan (D) Susan Wild (D) Matt Cartwright (D) Dan Meuser (R) Scott Perry (R) Lloyd Smucker (R) Summer Lee (D) John Joyce (R) Guy Reschenthaler (R) Glenn Thompson (R) Mike Kelly (R) Chris Deluzio (D) Délégations par États Alabama Alaska ...
Autoguider adalah sebuah alat bimbingan elektronik otomatis yang digunakan dalam astrophotography (biasanya dalam astronomi amatir) untuk menjaga teleskop menunjuk tepat pada objek yang difoto. Hal ini untuk mencegah objek dari melayang di bidang pandang selama-eksposur panjang yang akan membuat gambar kabur atau memanjang. Referensi Lodriguss, Jerry. Catching the Light. http://www.astropix.com/HTML/I_ASTROP/TRACKED/AUTOG.HTM. Covington, Michael. Digital SLR Astrophotography. New York: Cambr...
Keakuratan artikel ini diragukan dan artikel ini perlu diperiksa ulang dengan mencantumkan referensi yang dapat dipertanggungjawabkan. Diskusi terkait dapat dibaca pada the halaman pembicaraan. Harap pastikan akurasi artikel ini dengan sumber tepercaya. Lihat diskusi mengenai artikel ini di halaman diskusinya. (Pelajari cara dan kapan saatnya untuk menghapus pesan templat ini)Penyuntingan Artikel oleh pengguna baru atau anonim untuk saat ini tidak diizinkan.Lihat kebijakan pelindungan dan log...
La signora SkeffingtonBette Davis in una sequenza del filmTitolo originaleMr. Skeffington Paese di produzioneStati Uniti d'America Anno1944 Durata145 min Dati tecniciB/N Generedrammatico RegiaVincent Sherman SoggettoElizabeth von Arnim SceneggiaturaJulius J. Epstein e Philip G. Epstein ProduttoreJulius J. Epstein e Philip G. Epstein Casa di produzioneWarner Bros. Distribuzione in italianoENIC (1949) FotografiaErnest Haller MontaggioRalph Dawson MusicheFranz Waxman ScenografiaRobert M. Haas e ...
Decade of the Gregorian calendar From left, clockwise: Henry Clay introduces the Compromise of 1850 the U.S. Senate; Harriet Beecher Stowe publishes Uncle Tom’s Cabin; Russian forces fight against British, French and Ottoman forces in Sevastopol during the Crimean War; SS Arctic, an American steamship, sinks in the Atlantic Ocean after a collision with a French steamship, SS Vesta in 1854; The Panama Railroad opens in 1855 connecting the Pacific and Atlantic Oceans with a railroad in Centra...