Connectionism is an approach to the study of human mental processes and cognition that utilizes mathematical models known as connectionist networks or artificial neural networks.[1]
Connectionism has had many "waves" since its beginnings. The first wave appeared 1943 with Warren Sturgis McCulloch and Walter Pitts both focusing on comprehending neural circuitry through a formal and mathematical approach,[2] and Frank Rosenblatt who published the 1958 paper "The Perceptron: A Probabilistic Model For Information Storage and Organization in the Brain" in Psychological Review, while working at the Cornell Aeronautical Laboratory.[3]
The first wave ended with the 1969 book about the limitations of the original perceptron idea, written by Marvin Minsky and Seymour Papert, which contributed to discouraging major funding agencies in the US from investing in connectionist research.[4] With a few noteworthy deviations, most connectionist research entered a period of inactivity until the mid-1980s. The term connectionist model was reintroduced in a 1982 paper in the journal Cognitive Science by Jerome Feldman and Dana Ballard.
The second wave blossomed in the late 1980s, following a 1987 book about Parallel Distributed Processing by James L. McClelland, David E. Rumelhart et al., which introduced a couple of improvements to the simple perceptron idea, such as intermediate processors (now known as "hidden layers") alongside input and output units, and used a sigmoidactivation function instead of the old "all-or-nothing" function. Their work built upon that of John Hopfield, who was a key figure investigating the mathematical characteristics of sigmoid activation functions.[3] From the late 1980s to the mid-1990s, connectionism took on an almost revolutionary tone when Schneider,[5]Terence Horgan and Tienson posed the question of whether connectionism represented a fundamental shift in psychology and so-called "good old-fashioned AI," or GOFAI.[3] Some advantages of the second wave connectionist approach included its applicability to a broad array of functions, structural approximation to biological neurons, low requirements for innate structure, and capacity for graceful degradation.[6] Its disadvantages included the difficulty in deciphering how ANNs process information or account for the compositionality of mental representations, and a resultant difficulty explaining phenomena at a higher level.[7]
The current (third) wave has been marked by advances in deep learning, which have made possible the creation of large language models.[3] The success of deep-learning networks in the past decade has greatly increased the popularity of this approach, but the complexity and scale of such networks has brought with them increased interpretability problems.[8]
Basic principle
The central connectionist principle is that mental phenomena can be described by interconnected networks of simple and often uniform units. The form of the connections and the units can vary from model to model. For example, units in the network could represent neurons and the connections could represent synapses, as in the human brain. This principle has been seen as an alternative to GOFAI and the classical theories of mind based on symbolic computation, but the extent to which the two approaches are compatible has been the subject of much debate since their inception.[8]
Internal states of any network change over time due to neurons sending a signal to a succeeding layer of neurons in the case of a feedforward network, or to a previous layer in the case of a recurrent network. Discovery of non-linear activation functions has enabled the second wave of connectionism.
Any mental state can be described as a n-dimensional vector of numeric activation values over neural units in a network.
Memory and learning are created by modifying the 'weights' of the connections between neural units, generally represented as an n×mmatrix. The weights are adjusted according to some learning rule or algorithm, such as Hebbian learning.[9]
Most of the variety among the models comes from:
Interpretation of units: Units can be interpreted as neurons or groups of neurons.
Definition of activation: Activation can be defined in a variety of ways. For example, in a Boltzmann machine, the activation is interpreted as the probability of generating an action potential spike, and is determined via a logistic function on the sum of the inputs to a unit.
Learning algorithm: Different networks modify their connections differently. In general, any mathematically defined change in connection weights over time is referred to as the "learning algorithm".
Biological realism
Connectionist work in general does not need to be biologically realistic.[10][11][12][13][14][15][16] One area where connectionist models are thought to be biologically implausible is with respect to error-propagation networks that are needed to support learning,[17][18] but error propagation can explain some of the biologically-generated electrical activity seen at the scalp in event-related potentials such as the N400 and P600,[19] and this provides some biological support for one of the key assumptions of connectionist learning procedures. Many recurrent connectionist models also incorporate dynamical systems theory. Many researchers, such as the connectionist Paul Smolensky, have argued that connectionist models will evolve toward fully continuous, high-dimensional, non-linear, dynamic systems approaches.
Precursors
Precursors of the connectionist principles can be traced to early work in psychology, such as that of William James.[20] Psychological theories based on knowledge about the human brain were fashionable in the late 19th century. As early as 1869, the neurologist John Hughlings Jackson argued for multi-level, distributed systems. Following from this lead, Herbert Spencer's Principles of Psychology, 3rd edition (1872), and Sigmund Freud's Project for a Scientific Psychology (composed 1895) propounded connectionist or proto-connectionist theories. These tended to be speculative theories. But by the early 20th century, Edward Thorndike was writing about human learning that posited a connectionist type network.[21]
Hopfield networks had precursors in the Ising model due to Wilhelm Lenz (1920) and Ernst Ising (1925), though the Ising model conceived by them did not involve time. Monte Carlo simulations of Ising model required the advent of computers in the 1950s.[22]
The first wave
The first wave begun in 1943 with Warren Sturgis McCulloch and Walter Pitts both focusing on comprehending neural circuitry through a formal and mathematical approach. McCulloch and Pitts showed how neural systems could implement first-order logic: Their classic paper "A Logical Calculus of Ideas Immanent in Nervous Activity" (1943) is important in this development here. They were influenced by the work of Nicolas Rashevsky in the 1930s and symbolic logic in the style of Principia Mathematica.[23][3]
Hebb contributed greatly to speculations about neural functioning, and proposed a learning principle, Hebbian learning. Lashley argued for distributed representations as a result of his failure to find anything like a localized engram in years of lesion experiments. Friedrich Hayek independently conceived the model, first in a brief unpublished manuscript in 1920,[24][25] then expanded into a book in 1952.[26]
The Perceptron machines were proposed and built by Frank Rosenblatt, who published the 1958 paper “The Perceptron: A Probabilistic Model For Information Storage and Organization in the Brain” in Psychological Review, while working at the Cornell Aeronautical Laboratory. He cited Hebb, Hayek, Uttley, and Ashby as main influences.
The research group led by Widrow empirically searched for methods to train two-layered ADALINE networks (MADALINE), with limited success.[27][28]
A method to train multilayered perceptrons with arbitrary levels of trainable weights was published by Alexey Grigorevich Ivakhnenko and Valentin Lapa in 1965, called the Group Method of Data Handling. This method employs incremental layer by layer training based on regression analysis, where useless units in hidden layers are pruned with the help of a validation set.[29][30][31]
The first multilayered perceptrons trained by stochastic gradient descent[32] was published in 1967 by Shun'ichi Amari.[33] In computer experiments conducted by Amari's student Saito, a five layer MLP with two modifiable layers learned useful internal representations to classify non-linearily separable pattern classes.[30]
There was some conflict among artificial intelligence researchers as to what neural networks are useful for. Around late 1960s, there was a widespread lull in research and publications on neural networks, "the neural network winter", which lasted through the 1970s, during which the field of artificial intelligence turned towards symbolic methods. The publication of Perceptrons (1969) is typically regarded as a catalyst of this event.[35][36]
The second wave
The second wave begun in the early 1980s. Some key publications included (John Hopfield, 1982)[37] which popularized Hopfield networks, the 1986 paper that popularized backpropagation,[38] and the 1987 two-volume book about the Parallel Distributed Processing (PDP) by James L. McClelland, David E. Rumelhart et al., which has introduced a couple of improvements to the simple perceptron idea, such as intermediate processors (known as "hidden layers" now) alongside input and output units and using sigmoidactivation function instead of the old 'all-or-nothing' function.
Hopfield approached the field from the perspective of statistical mechanics, providing some early forms of mathematical rigor that increased the perceived respectability of the field.[3] Another important series of publications proved that neural networks are universal function approximators, which also provided some mathematical respectability.[39]
Some early popular demonstration projects appeared during this time. NETtalk (1987) learned to pronounce written English. It achieved popular success, appearing on the Today show.[40]TD-Gammon (1992) reached top human level in backgammon.[41]
Connectionism vs. computationalism debate
As connectionism became increasingly popular in the late 1980s, some researchers (including Jerry Fodor, Steven Pinker and others) reacted against it. They argued that connectionism, as then developing, threatened to obliterate what they saw as the progress being made in the fields of cognitive science and psychology by the classical approach of computationalism. Computationalism is a specific form of cognitivism that argues that mental activity is computational, that is, that the mind operates by performing purely formal operations on symbols, like a Turing machine. Some researchers argued that the trend in connectionism represented a reversion toward associationism and the abandonment of the idea of a language of thought, something they saw as mistaken. In contrast, those very tendencies made connectionism attractive for other researchers.
Connectionism and computationalism need not be at odds, but the debate in the late 1980s and early 1990s led to opposition between the two approaches. Throughout the debate, some researchers have argued that connectionism and computationalism are fully compatible, though full consensus on this issue has not been reached. Differences between the two approaches include the following:
Computationalists posit symbolic models that are structurally similar to underlying brain structure, whereas connectionists engage in "low-level" modeling, trying to ensure that their models resemble neurological structures.
Computationalists in general focus on the structure of explicit symbols (mental models) and syntactical rules for their internal manipulation, whereas connectionists focus on learning from environmental stimuli and storing this information in a form of connections between neurons.
Computationalists believe that internal mental activity consists of manipulation of explicit symbols, whereas connectionists believe that the manipulation of explicit symbols provides a poor model of mental activity.
Computationalists often posit domain specific symbolic sub-systems designed to support learning in specific areas of cognition (e.g., language, intentionality, number), whereas connectionists posit one or a small set of very general learning-mechanisms.
Despite these differences, some theorists have proposed that the connectionist architecture is simply the manner in which organic brains happen to implement the symbol-manipulation system. This is logically possible, as it is well known that connectionist models can implement symbol-manipulation systems of the kind used in computationalist models,[42] as indeed they must be able if they are to explain the human ability to perform symbol-manipulation tasks. Several cognitive models combining both symbol-manipulative and connectionist architectures have been proposed. Among them are Paul Smolensky's Integrated Connectionist/Symbolic Cognitive Architecture (ICS).[8][43] and Ron Sun's CLARION (cognitive architecture). But the debate rests on whether this symbol manipulation forms the foundation of cognition in general, so this is not a potential vindication of computationalism. Nonetheless, computational descriptions may be helpful high-level descriptions of cognition of logic, for example.
The debate was largely centred on logical arguments about whether connectionist networks could produce the syntactic structure observed in this sort of reasoning. This was later achieved although using fast-variable binding abilities outside of those standardly assumed in connectionist models.[42][44]
Part of the appeal of computational descriptions is that they are relatively easy to interpret, and thus may be seen as contributing to our understanding of particular mental processes, whereas connectionist models are in general more opaque, to the extent that they may be describable only in very general terms (such as specifying the learning algorithm, the number of units, etc.), or in unhelpfully low-level terms. In this sense, connectionist models may instantiate, and thereby provide evidence for, a broad theory of cognition (i.e., connectionism), without representing a helpful theory of the particular process that is being modelled. In this sense, the debate might be considered as to some extent reflecting a mere difference in the level of analysis in which particular theories are framed. Some researchers suggest that the analysis gap is the consequence of connectionist mechanisms giving rise to emergent phenomena that may be describable in computational terms.[45]
In the 2000s, the popularity of dynamical systems in philosophy of mind have added a new perspective on the debate;[46][47] some authors[which?] now argue that any split between connectionism and computationalism is more conclusively characterized as a split between computationalism and dynamical systems.
In 2014, Alex Graves and others from DeepMind published a series of papers describing a novel Deep Neural Network structure called the Neural Turing Machine[48] able to read symbols on a tape and store symbols in memory. Relational Networks, another Deep Network module published by DeepMind, are able to create object-like representations and manipulate them to answer complex questions. Relational Networks and Neural Turing Machines are further evidence that connectionism and computationalism need not be at odds.
Symbolism vs. connectionism debate
Smolensky's Subsymbolic Paradigm[49][50] has to meet the Fodor-Pylyshyn challenge[51][52][53][54] formulated by classical symbol theory for a convincing theory of cognition in modern connectionism. In order to be an adequate alternative theory of cognition, Smolensky's Subsymbolic Paradigm would have to explain the existence of systematicity or systematic relations in language cognition without the assumption that cognitive processes are causally sensitive to the classical constituent structure of mental representations. The subsymbolic paradigm, or connectionism in general, would thus have to explain the existence of systematicity and compositionality without relying on the mere implementation of a classical cognitive architecture. This challenge implies a dilemma: If the Subsymbolic Paradigm could contribute nothing to the systematicity and compositionality of mental representations, it would be insufficient as a basis for an alternative theory of cognition. However, if the Subsymbolic Paradigm's contribution to systematicity requires mental processes grounded in the classical constituent structure of mental representations, the theory of cognition it develops would be, at best, an implementation architecture of the classical model of symbol theory and thus not a genuine alternative (connectionist) theory of cognition.[55] The classical model of symbolism is characterized by (1) a combinatorial syntax and semantics of mental representations and (2) mental operations as structure-sensitive processes, based on the fundamental principle of syntactic and semantic constituent structure of mental representations as used in Fodor's "Language of Thought (LOT)".[56][57] This can be used to explain the following closely related properties of human cognition, namely its (1) productivity, (2) systematicity, (3) compositionality, and (4) inferential coherence.[58]
This challenge has been met in modern connectionism, for example, not only by Smolensky's "Integrated Connectionist/Symbolic (ICS) Cognitive Architecture",[59][60] but also by Werning and Maye's "Oscillatory Networks".[61][62][63] An overview of this is given for example by Bechtel & Abrahamsen,[64] Marcus[65] and Maurer.[66]
^ abcGarson, James (27 November 2018). Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University – via Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
^Anderson, James A.; Rosenfeld, Edward (1989). "Chapter 1: (1890) William James Psychology (Brief Course)". Neurocomputing: Foundations of Research. A Bradford Book. p. 1. ISBN978-0-262-51048-6.
^Hayek, Friedrich A. [1920] 1991. Beiträge zur Theorie der Entwicklung des Bewusstseins [Contributions to a theory of how consciousness develops]. Manuscript, translated by Grete Heinz.
^Widrow, B. (1962) Generalization and information storage in networks of ADALINE "neurons". In M. C. Yovits, G. T. Jacobi, & G. D. Goldstein (Ed.), Self-Organizing Svstems-1962 (pp. 435-461). Washington, DC: Spartan Books.
^P. Smolensky: On the proper treatment of connectionism. In: Behavioral and Brain Sciences. Band 11, 1988, S. 1-74.
^P. Smolensky: The constituent structure of connectionist mental states: a reply to Fodor and Pylyshyn. In: T. Horgan, J. Tienson (Hrsg.): Spindel Conference 1987: Connectionism and the Philosophy of Mind. The Southern Journal of Philosophy. Special Issue on Connectionism and the Foundations of Cognitive Science. Supplement. Band 26, 1988, S. 137-161.
^J.A. Fodor, Z.W. Pylyshyn: Connectionism and cognitive architecture: a critical analysis. Cognition. Band 28, 1988, S. 12-13, 33-50.
^J.A. Fodor, B. McLaughlin: Connectionism and the problem of systematicity: why Smolensky's solution doesn't work. Cognition. Band 35, 1990, S. 183-184.
^B. McLaughlin: The connectionism/classicism battle to win souls. Philosophical Studies, Band 71, 1993, S. 171-172.
^B. McLaughlin: Can an ICS architecture meet the systematicity and productivity challenges? In: P. Calvo, J. Symons (Hrsg.): The Architecture of Cognition. Rethinking Fodor and Pylyshyn's Systematicity Challenge. MIT Press, Cambridge/MA, London, 2014, S. 31-76.
^J.A. Fodor, B. McLaughlin: Connectionism and the problem of systematicity: Why Smolensky's solution doesn't work. Cognition. Band 35, 1990, S. 183-184.
^J.A. Fodor: The language of thought. Harvester Press, Sussex, 1976, ISBN 0-85527-309-7.
^J.A. Fodor: LOT 2: The language of thought revisited. Clarendon Press, Oxford, 2008, ISBN 0-19-954877-3.
^P. Smolenky: Reply: Constituent structure and explanation in an integrated connectionist / symbolic cognitive architecture. In: C. MacDonald, G. MacDonald (Hrsg.): Connectionism: Debates on psychological explanation. Blackwell Publishers. Oxford/UK, Cambridge/MA. Vol. 2, 1995, S. 224, 236-239, 242-244, 250-252, 282.
^P. Smolensky, G. Legendre: The Harmonic Mind: From Neural Computation to Optimality-Theoretic Grammar. Vol. 1: Cognitive Architecture. A Bradford Book, The MIT Press, Cambridge, London, 2006a, ISBN 0-262-19526-7, S. 65-67, 69-71, 74-75, 154-155, 159-202, 209-210, 235-267, 271-342, 513.
^M. Werning: Neuronal synchronization, covariation, and compositional representation. In: M. Werning, E. Machery, G. Schurz (Hrsg.): The compositionality of meaning and content. Vol. II: Applications to linguistics, psychology and neuroscience. Ontos Verlag, 2005, S. 283-312.
^M. Werning: Non-symbolic compositional representation and its neuronal foundation: towards an emulative semantics. In: M. Werning, W. Hinzen, E. Machery (Hrsg.): The Oxford Handbook of Compositionality. Oxford University Press, 2012, S. 633-654.
^A. Maye und M. Werning: Neuronal synchronization: from dynamics feature binding to compositional representations. Chaos and Complexity Letters, Band 2, S. 315-325.
^Bechtel, W., Abrahamsen, A.A. Connectionism and the Mind: Parallel Processing, Dynamics, and Evolution in Networks. 2nd Edition. Blackwell Publishers, Oxford. 2002
^G.F. Marcus: The algebraic mind. Integrating connectionism and cognitive science. Bradford Book, The MIT Press, Cambridge, 2001, ISBN 0-262-13379-2.
^H. Maurer: Cognitive science: Integrative synchronization mechanisms in cognitive neuroarchitectures of the modern connectionism. CRC Press, Boca Raton/FL, 2021, ISBN 978-1-351-04352-6. https://doi.org/10.1201/9781351043526
References
Feldman, Jerome and Ballard, Dana. Connectionist models and their properties(1982). Cognitive Science. V6, Iissue 3 , pp205-254.
Rumelhart, D.E., J.L. McClelland and the PDP Research Group (1986). Parallel Distributed Processing: Explorations in the Microstructure of Cognition. Volume 1: Foundations, Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press, ISBN978-0-262-68053-0
McClelland, J.L., D.E. Rumelhart and the PDP Research Group (1986). Parallel Distributed Processing: Explorations in the Microstructure of Cognition. Volume 2: Psychological and Biological Models, Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press, ISBN978-0-262-63110-5
Pinker, Steven and Mehler, Jacques (1988). Connections and Symbols, Cambridge MA: MIT Press, ISBN978-0-262-66064-8
Jeffrey L. Elman, Elizabeth A. Bates, Mark H. Johnson, Annette Karmiloff-Smith, Domenico Parisi, Kim Plunkett (1996). Rethinking Innateness: A connectionist perspective on development, Cambridge MA: MIT Press, ISBN978-0-262-55030-7
Marcus, Gary F. (2001). The Algebraic Mind: Integrating Connectionism and Cognitive Science (Learning, Development, and Conceptual Change), Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press, ISBN978-0-262-63268-3
Pour les articles homonymes, voir Séverine (homonymie). Séverine Informations générales Nom de naissance Josiane Grizeau Naissance 10 octobre 1948 (75 ans)Paris, Seine Activité principale Chanteuse Genre musical Pop Instruments Voix Labels Philips, Sony Music Site officiel severineofficiel.wixsite.com/severineofficiel modifier Séverine, née Josiane Grizeau le 10 octobre 1948 à Paris, est une chanteuse française. Biographie Josiane Grizeau, commence à chanter en 1967, sous le p...
Ralph Waldo Emerson Community Charter SchoolInformasiKepala SekolahDimone Watson[1]Jumlah siswa869AlamatLokasi1650 Selby AvenueLos Angeles, CaliforniaSitus webemersonms-lausd-ca.schoolloop.comMoto Ralph Waldo Emerson Community Charter School (dulunya Ralph Waldo Emerson Middle School dan umum disebut sebagai Emerson) adalah sebuah sekolah menengah tercarter di Los Angeles Unified School District, Westwood, Los Angeles, California, Amerika Serikat. Sekolah tersebut diran...
Pusat Polisi Militer Tentara Nasional IndonesiaLambang POM TNIAktif8 Desember 2015Negara IndonesiaTipe unitPolisi MiliterBagian dariTentara Nasional IndonesiaMarkasJakarta TimurMotoWijna Wira Yudha ChaktiBaret BIRU TokohKomandanMayor Jenderal TNI Yusri Nuryanto, S.IP.Wakil KomandanMarsekal Pertama TNI Bambang Suseno, CHRMP. Pusat Polisi Militer Tentara Nasional Indonesia atau biasa disingkat Puspom TNI merupakan salah satu fungsi teknis militer umum TNI yang berperan menyeleng...
Sepak bola pada Pekan Olahraga Daerah Sulawesi Selatan 2018Sepak bola pada Porda Sulsel 2018Sepak bola pada Porda Sulsel XVINegara IndonesiaTanggal penyelenggaraan24 – 30 September 2018Tempat penyelenggaraan Lapangan Andi Masapaila Desa Rajang, Kabupaten Pinrang Lapangan Malimpung, Kabupaten Pinrang Lapangan Pancasila Langnga, Kabupaten Pinrang Stadion Bau Massepe, Kabupaten Pinrang Juara bertahanPersiban BantaengJuara PS Toraja Utara(gelar ke-1)Tempat kedua Gaslut Luwu UtaraTempat ketiga P...
Artikel ini tidak memiliki referensi atau sumber tepercaya sehingga isinya tidak bisa dipastikan. Tolong bantu perbaiki artikel ini dengan menambahkan referensi yang layak. Tulisan tanpa sumber dapat dipertanyakan dan dihapus sewaktu-waktu.Cari sumber: Oh My Venus – berita · surat kabar · buku · cendekiawan · JSTOR Oh My VenusPoster promosiGenreAsmara Drama KomediDitulis olehKim Eun-jiSutradaraKim Hyung-sukPemeranSo Ji-sub Shin Min-aNegara asalKorea Se...
2011 Russian legislative election ← 2007 4 December 2011 2016 → All 450 seats in the State Duma226 seats needed for a majorityTurnout60.10% Party Leader % Seats +/– United Russia Vladimir Putin 50.10 238 −77 Communist Gennady Zyuganov 19.50 92 +35 SR Nikolai Levichev 13.46 64 +26 LDPR Vladimir Zhirinovsky 11.86 56 +16 This lists parties that won seats. See the complete results below.Winning party by municipality Chairman of the State Duma before Chairman of the Stat...
Ricky Martin awards and nominationsMartin performing during the Música + Alma + Sexo World Tour, April 2011Awards and nominationsAward Wins NominationsALMA Awards 5 8American Music Awards 2 5ASCAP Awards 18 18Billboard Music Awards 3 3Billboard Latin Music Awards 9 22Blockbuster Entertainment Awards 3 6BMI Awards 20 20Emmy Awards 0 1GLAAD Media Awards 3 4Grammy Awards 2 8International Dance Music Awards 2 4Japan Gold Disc Awards 1 1Latin Grammy Awards 5 23MTV Asia Awards 2 2MTV Europe Music...
Private university in Provo, Utah, US BYU redirects here. For other uses, see BYU (disambiguation). It has been suggested that Y Magazine be merged into this article. (Discuss) Proposed since February 2024. Brigham Young UniversityFormer nameBrigham Young Academy (1875–1903)MottoNo official motto[1]Unofficial mottoes include:The glory of God is intelligence[2]Enter to learn, go forth to serve[3]The world is our campus[4]TypePrivate research universityEstablis...
Getreidegasse Getreidegasse adalah sebuah jalan sempit yang terletak pusat kota bersejarah Salzburg di Austria. Jalan yang hanya dapat dilewati oleh pejalan kaki ini merupakan pusat perbelanjaan sekaligus tempat wisata. Gedung paling terkenal yang berada di jalan ini adalah tempat kelahiran musisi Wolfgang Amadeus Mozart di Getreidegasse nomor 9, dan ia tinggal di rumah tersebut hingga ia berumur 17 tahun. Jalan ini pertama kali disebutkan dalam sejarah dengan nama Trabegasse sekitar tahun 11...
Un nombre Oméga de Chaitin est une suite de bits représentant, sous forme concentrée, la solution du problème de l'arrêt pour tous les programmes d'une machine de Turing universelle donnée. En théorie algorithmique de l'information, une constante Oméga de Chaitin (nombres définis et étudiés par Gregory Chaitin) caractérise de manière univoque et mathématiquement précise un nombre réel, qui possède la particularité d'être aléatoire et de ne pas être calculable au sens de T...
Pad used for warming of parts of the body in order to manage pain HotBag redirects here. For the container used to keep pizzas warm, see Pizza delivery § Delivery bags. A heating pad is a pad used for warming of parts of the body in order to manage pain. Localized application of heat causes the blood vessels in that area to dilate, enhancing perfusion to the targeted tissue. Types of heating pads include electrical, chemical and hot water bottles. Specialized heating pads (mats) are als...
Heinrich von Kleist Född18 oktober 1777[1][2][3]Frankfurt an der Oder[4][5]Död21 november 1811[1][2][3] (34 år)Kleiner Wannsee[5], TysklandBegravdWannseeMedborgare iKonungariket PreussenUtbildad vidBrandenburgische Universität Frankfurt SysselsättningDramatiker[6], författare[6][7], diktarjurist, poet[5][6], novellförfattare[5], publicistNoterbara verkDen sönderslagna krukan och Markisinnan von O.FöräldrarJoachim Friedrich von Kleist[8]Juliane Ulrike von Pannwitz[8]Na...
Questa voce o sezione sull'argomento nobili è ritenuta da controllare. Motivo: libri inseriti come fonti ma non riportati in bibliografia Partecipa alla discussione e/o correggi la voce. Luisa di HannoverLa regina Luisa ritratta da Carl Gustaf Pilo, 1747Galleria d'Arte Nazionale, CopenaghenRegina consorte di Danimarca e NorvegiaStemma In carica6 agosto 1746 –19 dicembre 1751 PredecessoreSofia Maddalena di Brandeburgo-Kulmbach SuccessoreGiuliana Maria di Brunswick-Lüneburg ...
Varieties of English native to the United States U.S. English redirects here. For the political organization, see U.S. English (organization). For the English language throughout North America, see North American English. For other uses, see American English (disambiguation). American EnglishDistribution of American English by state in 2000RegionUnited StatesNative speakers242 million, all varieties of English in the United States (2019)[citation needed]67.3 million L2 speakers o...
Town in Rhineland-Palatinate, GermanyBad Sobernheim Town Coat of armsLocation of Bad Sobernheim within Bad Kreuznach district Bad Sobernheim Show map of GermanyBad Sobernheim Show map of Rhineland-PalatinateCoordinates: 49°47′14″N 07°39′10″E / 49.78722°N 7.65278°E / 49.78722; 7.65278CountryGermanyStateRhineland-PalatinateDistrictBad Kreuznach Municipal assoc.Bad SobernheimGovernment • Mayor (2019–24) Michael Greiner[1] (SPD)Area...
Ceramic material This article is about the ceramic material. For other uses, see Porcelain (disambiguation). Chinese Jingdezhen porcelain moonflask with underglaze blue and red. Qianlong period, 1736 to 1796 A lithophane exploits the translucency of porcelain Nymphenburg porcelain group modelled by Franz Anton Bustelli, 1756 PorcelainChinese瓷TranscriptionsStandard MandarinHanyu PinyincíWade–Gilestz'ŭ2IPA[tsʰɹ̩̌]Yue: CantoneseYale RomanizationchìhJyutpingci4IPA[tsʰi˩]Southern ...
Music theory concept C7 is transpositionally equivalent to the F♯7, the leading tones resolve inversionally (E-B♭ resolves to F-A, A♯-E resolves to B-D♯) Play F-C7-F, F-F♯7-F, B-F♯7-B, then B-C7-Bⓘ The tritone substitution is a common chord substitution found in both jazz and classical music. Where jazz is concerned, it was the precursor to more complex substitution patterns like Coltrane changes. Tritone substitutions are sometimes used in improvis...