Although the function is not defined at zero, as x becomes closer and closer to zero, becomes arbitrarily close to 1. In other words, the limit of as x approaches zero, equals 1.
In mathematics, the limit of a function is a fundamental concept in calculus and analysis concerning the behavior of that function near a particular input which may or may not be in the domain of the function.
Formal definitions, first devised in the early 19th century, are given below. Informally, a function f assigns an outputf(x) to every input x. We say that the function has a limit L at an input p, if f(x) gets closer and closer to L as x moves closer and closer to p. More specifically, the output value can be made arbitrarily close to L if the input to f is taken sufficiently close to p. On the other hand, if some inputs very close to p are taken to outputs that stay a fixed distance apart, then we say the limit does not exist.
The notion of a limit has many applications in modern calculus. In particular, the many definitions of continuity employ the concept of limit: roughly, a function is continuous if all of its limits agree with the values of the function. The concept of limit also appears in the definition of the derivative: in the calculus of one variable, this is the limiting value of the slope of secant lines to the graph of a function.
History
Although implicit in the development of calculus of the 17th and 18th centuries, the modern idea of the limit of a function goes back to Bolzano who, in 1817, introduced the basics of the epsilon-delta technique (see (ε, δ)-definition of limit below) to define continuous functions. However, his work was not known during his lifetime.[1]
In his 1821 book Cours d'analyse, Augustin-Louis Cauchy discussed variable quantities, infinitesimals and limits, and defined continuity of by saying that an infinitesimal change in x necessarily produces an infinitesimal change in y, while Grabiner claims that he used a rigorous epsilon-delta definition in proofs.[2] In 1861, Weierstrass first introduced the epsilon-delta definition of limit in the form it is usually written today.[3] He also introduced the notations and [4]
The modern notation of placing the arrow below the limit symbol is due to Hardy, which is introduced in his book A Course of Pure Mathematics in 1908.[5]
Motivation
Imagine a person walking on a landscape represented by the graph y = f(x). Their horizontal position is given by x, much like the position given by a map of the land or by a global positioning system. Their altitude is given by the coordinate y. Suppose they walk towards a position x = p, as they get closer and closer to this point, they will notice that their altitude approaches a specific value L. If asked about the altitude corresponding to x = p, they would reply by saying y = L.
What, then, does it mean to say, their altitude is approaching L? It means that their altitude gets nearer and nearer to L—except for a possible small error in accuracy. For example, suppose we set a particular accuracy goal for our traveler: they must get within ten meters of L. They report back that indeed, they can get within ten vertical meters of L, arguing that as long as they are within fifty horizontal meters of p, their altitude is always within ten meters of L.
The accuracy goal is then changed: can they get within one vertical meter? Yes, supposing that they are able to move within five horizontal meters of p, their altitude will always remain within one meter from the target altitude L. Summarizing the aforementioned concept we can say that the traveler's altitude approaches L as their horizontal position approaches p, so as to say that for every target accuracy goal, however small it may be, there is some neighbourhood of p where all (not just some) altitudes correspond to all the horizontal positions, except maybe the horizontal position p itself, in that neighbourhood fulfill that accuracy goal.
The initial informal statement can now be explicated:
The limit of a function f(x) as x approaches p is a number L with the following property: given any target distance from L, there is a distance from p within which the values of f(x) remain within the target distance.
In fact, this explicit statement is quite close to the formal definition of the limit of a function, with values in a topological space.
More specifically, to say that
is to say that f(x) can be made as close to L as desired, by making x close enough, but not equal, to p.
The following definitions, known as (ε, δ)-definitions, are the generally accepted definitions for the limit of a function in various contexts.
Functions of a single variable
(ε, δ)-definition of limit
Suppose is a function defined on the real line, and there are two real numbers p and L. One would say that the limit of f, as x approaches p, is L and written[6]
or alternatively, say f(x) tends to L as x tends to p, and written:
if the following property holds: for every real ε > 0, there exists a real δ > 0 such that for all real x, 0 < |x − p| < δ implies |f(x) − L| < ε.[6] Symbolically,
For example, we may say
because for every real ε > 0, we can take δ = ε/4, so that for all real x, if 0 < |x − 2| < δ, then |4x + 1 − 9| < ε.
A more general definition applies for functions defined on subsets of the real line. Let S be a subset of Let be a real-valued function. Let p be a point such that there exists some open interval (a, b) containing p with It is then said that the limit of f as x approaches p is L, if:
For every real ε > 0, there exists a real δ > 0 such that for all x ∈ (a, b), 0 < |x − p| < δ implies that |f(x) − L| < ε.
Or, symbolically:
For example, we may say
because for every real ε > 0, we can take δ = ε, so that for all real x ≥ −3, if 0 < |x − 1| < δ, then |f(x) − 2| < ε. In this example, S = [−3, ∞) contains open intervals around the point 1 (for example, the interval (0, 2)).
Here, note that the value of the limit does not depend on f being defined at p, nor on the value f(p)—if it is defined. For example, let
because for every ε > 0, we can take δ = ε/2, so that for all real x ≠ 1, if 0 < |x − 1| < δ, then |f(x) − 3| < ε. Note that here f(1) is undefined.
In fact, a limit can exist in which equals where int S is the interior of S, and iso Sc are the isolated points of the complement of S. In our previous example where We see, specifically, this definition of limit allows a limit to exist at 1, but not 0 or 2.
The letters ε and δ can be understood as "error" and "distance". In fact, Cauchy used ε as an abbreviation for "error" in some of his work,[2] though in his definition of continuity, he used an infinitesimal rather than either ε or δ (see Cours d'Analyse). In these terms, the error (ε) in the measurement of the value at the limit can be made as small as desired, by reducing the distance (δ) to the limit point. As discussed below, this definition also works for functions in a more general context. The idea that δ and ε represent distances helps suggest these generalizations.
Alternatively, x may approach p from above (right) or below (left), in which case the limits may be written as
or
respectively. If these limits exist at p and are equal there, then this can be referred to as the limit of f(x) at p.[7] If the one-sided limits exist at p, but are unequal, then there is no limit at p (i.e., the limit at p does not exist). If either one-sided limit does not exist at p, then the limit at p also does not exist.
A formal definition is as follows. The limit of f as x approaches p from above is L if:
For every ε > 0, there exists a δ > 0 such that whenever 0 < x − p < δ, we have |f(x) − L| < ε.
The limit of f as x approaches p from below is L if:
For every ε > 0, there exists a δ > 0 such that whenever 0 < p − x < δ, we have |f(x) − L| < ε.
If the limit does not exist, then the oscillation of f at p is non-zero.
More general definition using limit points and subsets
Limits can also be defined by approaching from subsets of the domain.
In general:[8] Let be a real-valued function defined on some Let p be a limit point of some —that is, p is the limit of some sequence of elements of T distinct from p. Then we say the limit of f, as x approaches p from values in T, is L, written
if the following holds:
For every ε > 0, there exists a δ > 0 such that for all x ∈ T, 0 < |x − p| < δ implies that |f(x) − L| < ε.
Note, T can be any subset of S, the domain of f. And the limit might depend on the selection of T. This generalization includes as special cases limits on an interval, as well as left-handed limits of real-valued functions (e.g., by taking T to be an open interval of the form (–∞, a)), and right-handed limits (e.g., by taking T to be an open interval of the form (a, ∞)). It also extends the notion of one-sided limits to the included endpoints of (half-)closed intervals, so the square root function can have limit 0 as x approaches 0 from above:
since for every ε > 0, we may take δ = ε2 such that for all x ≥ 0, if 0 < |x − 0| < δ, then |f(x) − 0| < ε.
This definition allows a limit to be defined at limit points of the domain S, if a suitable subset T which has the same limit point is chosen.
Notably, the previous two-sided definition works on which is a subset of the limit points of S.
For example, let The previous two-sided definition would work at but it wouldn't work at 0 or 2, which are limit points of S.
Deleted versus non-deleted limits
The definition of limit given here does not depend on how (or whether) f is defined at p. Bartle[9] refers to this as a deleted limit, because it excludes the value of f at p. The corresponding non-deleted limit does depend on the value of f at p, if p is in the domain of f. Let be a real-valued function. The non-deleted limit of f, as x approaches p, is L if
For every ε > 0, there exists a δ > 0 such that for all x ∈ S, |x − p| < δ implies |f(x) − L| < ε.
The definition is the same, except that the neighborhood |x − p| < δ now includes the point p, in contrast to the deleted neighborhood0 < |x − p| < δ. This makes the definition of a non-deleted limit less general. One of the advantages of working with non-deleted limits is that they allow to state the theorem about limits of compositions without any constraints on the functions (other than the existence of their non-deleted limits).[10]
Bartle[9] notes that although by "limit" some authors do mean this non-deleted limit, deleted limits are the most popular.[11]
Examples
Non-existence of one-sided limit(s)
The function
has no limit at x0 = 1 (the left-hand limit does not exist due to the oscillatory nature of the sine function, and the right-hand limit does not exist due to the asymptotic behaviour of the reciprocal function, see picture), but has a limit at every other x-coordinate.
The function
(a.k.a., the Dirichlet function) has no limit at any x-coordinate.
Non-equality of one-sided limits
The function
has a limit at every non-zero x-coordinate (the limit equals 1 for negative x and equals 2 for positive x). The limit at x = 0 does not exist (the left-hand limit equals 1, whereas the right-hand limit equals 2).
Limits at only one point
The functions
and
both have a limit at x = 0 and it equals 0.
Limits at countably many points
The function
has a limit at any x-coordinate of the form where n is any integer.
Limits involving infinity
Limits at infinity
Let be a function defined on The limit of f as x approaches infinity is L, denoted
means that:
For every ε > 0, there exists a c > 0 such that whenever +x > c, we have |f(x) − L| < ε.
Similarly, the limit of f as x approaches minus infinity is L, denoted
means that:
For every ε > 0, there exists a c > 0 such that whenever x < −c, we have |f(x) − L| < ε.
For example,
because for every ε > 0, we can take c = 3/ε such that for all real x, if x > c, then |f(x) − 4| < ε.
Another example is that
because for every ε > 0, we can take c = max{1, −ln(ε)} such that for all real x, if x < −c, then |f(x) − 0| < ε.
Infinite limits
For a function whose values grow without bound, the function diverges and the usual limit does not exist. However, in this case one may introduce limits with infinite values.
Let be a function defined on The statement the limit of f as x approaches p is infinity, denoted
means that:
For every N > 0, there exists a δ > 0 such that whenever 0 < |x − p| < δ, we have f(x) > N.
The statement the limit of f as x approaches p is minus infinity, denoted
means that:
For every N > 0, there exists a δ > 0 such that whenever 0 < |x − p| < δ, we have f(x) < −N.
For example,
because for every N > 0, we can take such that for all real x > 0, if 0 < x − 1 < δ, then f(x) > N.
These ideas can be used together to produce definitions for different combinations, such as
or
For example,
because for every N > 0, we can take δ = e−N such that for all real x > 0, if 0 < x − 0 < δ, then f(x) < −N.
Limits involving infinity are connected with the concept of asymptotes.
These notions of a limit attempt to provide a metric space interpretation to limits at infinity. In fact, they are consistent with the topological space definition of limit if
a neighborhood of −∞ is defined to contain an interval[−∞, c) for some
a neighborhood of ∞ is defined to contain an interval (c, ∞] where and
a neighborhood of is defined in the normal way metric space
In this case, is a topological space and any function of the form with is subject to the topological definition of a limit. Note that with this topological definition, it is easy to define infinite limits at finite points, which have not been defined above in the metric sense.
Alternative notation
Many authors[12] allow for the projectively extended real line to be used as a way to include infinite values as well as extended real line. With this notation, the extended real line is given as and the projectively extended real line is where a neighborhood of ∞ is a set of the form The advantage is that one only needs three definitions for limits (left, right, and central) to cover all the cases.
As presented above, for a completely rigorous account, we would need to consider 15 separate cases for each combination of infinities (five directions: −∞, left, central, right, and +∞; three bounds: −∞, finite, or +∞). There are also noteworthy pitfalls. For example, when working with the extended real line, does not possess a central limit (which is normal):
In contrast, when working with the projective real line, infinities (much like 0) are unsigned, so, the central limit does exist in that context:
In fact there are a plethora of conflicting formal systems in use.
In certain applications of numerical differentiation and integration, it is, for example, convenient to have signed zeroes.
A simple reason has to do with the converse of namely, it is convenient for to be considered true.
Such zeroes can be seen as an approximation to infinitesimals.
Limits at infinity for rational functions
There are three basic rules for evaluating limits at infinity for a rational function (where p and q are polynomials):
If the degree of p is greater than the degree of q, then the limit is positive or negative infinity depending on the signs of the leading coefficients;
If the degree of p and q are equal, the limit is the leading coefficient of p divided by the leading coefficient of q;
If the degree of p is less than the degree of q, the limit is 0.
If the limit at infinity exists, it represents a horizontal asymptote at y = L. Polynomials do not have horizontal asymptotes; such asymptotes may however occur with rational functions.
Functions of more than one variable
Ordinary limits
By noting that |x − p| represents a distance, the definition of a limit can be extended to functions of more than one variable. In the case of a function defined on we defined the limit as follows: the limit of f as (x, y) approaches (p, q) is L, written
if the following condition holds:
For every ε > 0, there exists a δ > 0 such that for all x in S and y in T, whenever we have |f(x, y) − L| < ε,[13]
or formally:
Here is the Euclidean distance between (x, y) and (p, q). (This can in fact be replaced by any norm||(x, y) − (p, q)||, and be extended to any number of variables.)
For example, we may say
because for every ε > 0, we can take such that for all real x ≠ 0 and real y ≠ 0, if then |f(x, y) − 0| < ε.
Similar to the case in single variable, the value of f at (p, q) does not matter in this definition of limit.
For such a multivariable limit to exist, this definition requires the value of f approaches L along every possible path approaching (p, q).[14] In the above example, the function
satisfies this condition. This can be seen by considering the polar coordinates
which gives
Here θ = θ(r) is a function of r which controls the shape of the path along which f is approaching (p, q). Since cos θ is bounded between [−1, 1], by the sandwich theorem, this limit tends to 0.
In contrast, the function
does not have a limit at (0, 0). Taking the path (x, y) = (t, 0) → (0, 0), we obtain
while taking the path (x, y) = (t, t) → (0, 0), we obtain
Since the two values do not agree, f does not tend to a single value as (x, y) approaches (0, 0).
Multiple limits
Although less commonly used, there is another type of limit for a multivariable function, known as the multiple limit. For a two-variable function, this is the double limit.[15] Let be defined on we say the double limit of f as x approaches p and y approaches q is L, written
if the following condition holds:
For every ε > 0, there exists a δ > 0 such that for all x in S and y in T, whenever 0 < |x − p| < δ and 0 < |y − q| < δ, we have |f(x, y) − L| < ε.[15]
For such a double limit to exist, this definition requires the value of f approaches L along every possible path approaching (p, q), excluding the two lines x = p and y = q. As a result, the multiple limit is a weaker notion than the ordinary limit: if the ordinary limit exists and equals L, then the multiple limit exists and also equals L. The converse is not true: the existence of the multiple limits does not imply the existence of the ordinary limit. Consider the example
where
but
does not exist.
If the domain of f is restricted to then the two definitions of limits coincide.[15]
Multiple limits at infinity
The concept of multiple limit can extend to the limit at infinity, in a way similar to that of a single variable function. For we say the double limit of f as x and y approaches infinity is L, written
if the following condition holds:
For every ε > 0, there exists a c > 0 such that for all x in S and y in T, whenever x > c and y > c, we have |f(x, y) − L| < ε.
We say the double limit of f as x and y approaches minus infinity is L, written
if the following condition holds:
For every ε > 0, there exists a c > 0 such that x in S and y in T, whenever x < −c and y < −c, we have |f(x, y) − L| < ε.
Let Instead of taking limit as (x, y) → (p, q), we may consider taking the limit of just one variable, say, x → p, to obtain a single-variable function of y, namely In fact, this limiting process can be done in two distinct ways. The first one is called pointwise limit. We say the pointwise limit of f as x approaches p is g, denoted
or
Alternatively, we may say f tends to g pointwise as x approaches p, denoted
or
This limit exists if the following holds:
For every ε > 0 and every fixed y in T, there exists a δ(ε, y) > 0 such that for all x in S, whenever 0 < |x − p| < δ, we have |f(x, y) − g(y)| < ε.[16]
Here, δ = δ(ε, y) is a function of both ε and y. Each δ is chosen for a specific point of y. Hence we say the limit is pointwise in y. For example,
has a pointwise limit of constant zero function
because for every fixed y, the limit is clearly 0. This argument fails if y is not fixed: if y is very close to π/2, the value of the fraction may deviate from 0.
This leads to another definition of limit, namely the uniform limit. We say the uniform limit of f on T as x approaches p is g, denoted
or
Alternatively, we may say f tends to g uniformly on T as x approaches p, denoted
or
This limit exists if the following holds:
For every ε > 0, there exists a δ(ε) > 0 such that for all x in S and y in T, whenever 0 < |x − p| < δ, we have |f(x, y) − g(y)| < ε.[16]
Here, δ = δ(ε) is a function of only ε but not y. In other words, δ is uniformly applicable to all y in T. Hence we say the limit is uniform in y. For example,
has a uniform limit of constant zero function
because for all real y, cos y is bounded between [−1, 1]. Hence no matter how y behaves, we may use the sandwich theorem to show that the limit is 0.
Let We may consider taking the limit of just one variable, say, x → p, to obtain a single-variable function of y, namely and then take limit in the other variable, namely y → q, to get a number L. Symbolically,
This limit is known as iterated limit of the multivariable function.[17] The order of taking limits may affect the result, i.e.,
in general.
A sufficient condition of equality is given by the Moore-Osgood theorem, which requires the limit to be uniform on T.[18]
Functions on metric spaces
Suppose M and N are subsets of metric spacesA and B, respectively, and f : M → N is defined between M and N, with x ∈ M, p a limit point of M and L ∈ N. It is said that the limit of f as x approaches p is L and write
if the following property holds:
For every ε > 0, there exists a δ > 0 such that for all points x ∈ M, 0 < dA(x, p) < δ implies dB(f(x), L) < ε.[19]
Again, note that p need not be in the domain of f, nor does L need to be in the range of f, and even if f(p) is defined it need not be equal to L.
For every ε > 0, there exists a δ > 0 such that for all x in S and y in T, implies [20]
In this example, the function concerned are finite-dimension vector-valued function. In this case, the limit theorem for vector-valued function states that if the limit of each component exists, then the limit of a vector-valued function equals the vector with each component taken the limit:[20]
Manhattan metric
One might also want to consider spaces other than Euclidean space. An example would be the Manhattan space. Consider such that
Then, under the Manhattan metric,
if the following holds:
For every ε > 0, there exists a δ > 0 such that for all x in S, 0 < |x − p| < δ implies |f1 − L1| + |f2 − L2| < ε.
Since this is also a finite-dimension vector-valued function, the limit theorem stated above also applies.[21]
Uniform metric
Finally, we will discuss the limit in function space, which has infinite dimensions. Consider a function f(x, y) in the function space We want to find out as x approaches p, how f(x, y) will tend to another function g(y), which is in the function space The "closeness" in this function space may be measured under the uniform metric.[22] Then, we will say the uniform limit of f on T as x approaches p is g and write
or
if the following holds:
For every ε > 0, there exists a δ > 0 such that for all x in S, 0 < |x − p| < δ implies
In fact, one can see that this definition is equivalent to that of the uniform limit of a multivariable function introduced in the previous section.
Suppose X and Y are topological spaces with Y a Hausdorff space. Let p be a limit point of Ω ⊆ X, and L ∈ Y. For a function f : Ω → Y, it is said that the limit of f as x approaches p is L, written
if the following property holds:
For every open neighborhoodV of L, there exists an open neighborhood U of p such that f(U ∩ Ω − {p}) ⊆ V.
This last part of the definition can also be phrased "there exists an open punctured neighbourhoodU of p such that f(U ∩ Ω) ⊆ V".
The domain of f does not need to contain p. If it does, then the value of f at p is irrelevant to the definition of the limit. In particular, if the domain of f is X − {p} (or all of X), then the limit of f as x → p exists and is equal to L if, for all subsets Ω of X with limit point p, the limit of the restriction of f to Ω exists and is equal to L. Sometimes this criterion is used to establish the non-existence of the two-sided limit of a function on by showing that the one-sided limits either fail to exist or do not agree. Such a view is fundamental in the field of general topology, where limits and continuity at a point are defined in terms of special families of subsets, called filters, or generalized sequences known as nets.
Alternatively, the requirement that Y be a Hausdorff space can be relaxed to the assumption that Y be a general topological space, but then the limit of a function may not be unique. In particular, one can no longer talk about the limit of a function at a point, but rather a limit or the set of limits at a point.
A function is continuous at a limit point p of and in its domain if and only if f(p) is the (or, in the general case, a) limit of f(x) as x tends to p.
There is another type of limit of a function, namely the sequential limit. Let f : X → Y be a mapping from a topological space X into a Hausdorff space Y, p ∈ X a limit point of X and L ∈ Y. The sequential limit of f as x tends to p is L if
If L is the limit (in the sense above) of f as x approaches p, then it is a sequential limit as well, however the converse need not hold in general. If in addition X is metrizable, then L is the sequential limit of f as x approaches p if and only if it is the limit (in the sense above) of f as x approaches p.
Other characterizations
In terms of sequences
For functions on the real line, one way to define the limit of a function is in terms of the limit of sequences. (This definition is usually attributed to Eduard Heine.) In this setting:
if, and only if, for all sequences xn (with xn not equal to a for all n) converging to a the sequence f(xn) converges to L. It was shown by Sierpiński in 1916 that proving the equivalence of this definition and the definition above, requires and is equivalent to a weak form of the axiom of choice. Note that defining what it means for a sequence xn to converge to a requires the epsilon, delta method.
Similarly as it was the case of Weierstrass's definition, a more general Heine definition applies to functions defined on subsets of the real line. Let f be a real-valued function with the domain Dm(f ). Let a be the limit of a sequence of elements of Dm(f ) \ {a}. Then the limit (in this sense) of f is L as x approaches p
if for every sequence xn ∈ Dm(f ) \ {a} (so that for all n, xn is not equal to a) that converges to a, the sequence f(xn) converges to L. This is the same as the definition of a sequential limit in the preceding section obtained by regarding the subset Dm(f ) of as a metric space with the induced metric.
In non-standard calculus
In non-standard calculus the limit of a function is defined by:
if and only if for all is infinitesimal whenever x − a is infinitesimal. Here are the hyperreal numbers and f* is the natural extension of f to the non-standard real numbers. Keisler proved that such a hyperreal definition of limit reduces the quantifier complexity by two quantifiers.[23] On the other hand, Hrbacek writes that for the definitions to be valid for all hyperreal numbers they must implicitly be grounded in the ε-δ method, and claims that, from the pedagogical point of view, the hope that non-standard calculus could be done without ε-δ methods cannot be realized in full.[24]
Bŀaszczyk et al. detail the usefulness of microcontinuity in developing a transparent definition of uniform continuity, and characterize Hrbacek's criticism as a "dubious lament".[25]
In terms of nearness
At the 1908 international congress of mathematics F. Riesz introduced an alternate way defining limits and continuity in concept called "nearness".[26] A point x is defined to be near a set if for every r > 0 there is a point a ∈ A so that |x − a| < r. In this setting the
if and only if for all L is near f(A) whenever a is near A.
Here f(A) is the set This definition can also be extended to metric and topological spaces.
The notion of the limit of a function is very closely related to the concept of continuity. A function f is said to be continuous at c if it is both defined at c and its value at c equals the limit of f as x approaches c:
We have here assumed that c is a limit point of the domain of f.
Properties
If a function f is real-valued, then the limit of f at p is L if and only if both the right-handed limit and left-handed limit of f at p exist and are equal to L.[27]
The function f is continuous at p if and only if the limit of f(x) as x approaches p exists and is equal to f(p). If f : M → N is a function between metric spaces M and N, then it is equivalent that f transforms every sequence in M which converges towards p into a sequence in N which converges towards f(p).
If N is a normed vector space, then the limit operation is linear in the following sense: if the limit of f(x) as x approaches p is L and the limit of g(x) as x approaches p is P, then the limit of f(x) + g(x) as x approaches p is L + P. If a is a scalar from the base field, then the limit of af(x) as x approaches p is aL.
If f and g are real-valued (or complex-valued) functions, then taking the limit of an operation on f(x) and g(x) (e.g., f + g, f − g, f × g, f / g, f g) under certain conditions is compatible with the operation of limits of f(x) and g(x). This fact is often called the algebraic limit theorem. The main condition needed to apply the following rules is that the limits on the right-hand sides of the equations exist (in other words, these limits are finite values including 0). Additionally, the identity for division requires that the denominator on the right-hand side is non-zero (division by 0 is not defined), and the identity for exponentiation requires that the base is positive, or zero while the exponent is positive (finite).
These rules are also valid for one-sided limits, including when p is ∞ or −∞. In each rule above, when one of the limits on the right is ∞ or −∞, the limit on the left may sometimes still be determined by the following rules.
In other cases the limit on the left may still exist, although the right-hand side, called an indeterminate form, does not allow one to determine the result. This depends on the functions f and g. These indeterminate forms are:
In general, from knowing that and it does not follow that
However, this "chain rule" does hold if one of the following additional conditions holds:
f(b) = c (that is, f is continuous at b), or
g does not take the value b near a (that is, there exists a δ > 0 such that if 0 < |x − a| < δ then |g(x) − b| > 0).
As an example of this phenomenon, consider the following function that violates both additional restrictions:
Since the value at f(0) is a removable discontinuity,
for all a.
Thus, the naïve chain rule would suggest that the limit of f(f(x)) is 0. However, it is the case that
and so
for all a.
This can be proven by dividing both the numerator and denominator by xn. If the numerator is a polynomial of higher degree, the limit does not exist. If the denominator is of higher degree, the limit is 0.
This rule uses derivatives to find limits of indeterminate forms0/0 or ±∞/∞, and only applies to such cases. Other indeterminate forms may be manipulated into this form. Given two functions f(x) and g(x), defined over an open intervalI containing the desired limit point c, then if:
or and
and are differentiable over and
for all and
exists,
then:
Normally, the first condition is the most important one.
For example:
Summations and integrals
Specifying an infinite bound on a summation or integral is a common shorthand for specifying a limit.
A short way to write the limit
is An important example of limits of sums such as these are series.
^ abcZakon, Elias (2011), "Chapter 4. Function Limits and Continuity", Mathematical Anaylysis, Volume I, University of Windsor, pp. 219–220, ISBN9781617386473
Artikel ini tidak memiliki referensi atau sumber tepercaya sehingga isinya tidak bisa dipastikan. Tolong bantu perbaiki artikel ini dengan menambahkan referensi yang layak. Tulisan tanpa sumber dapat dipertanyakan dan dihapus sewaktu-waktu.Cari sumber: Koteka – berita · surat kabar · buku · cendekiawan · JSTOR Koteka Koteka adalah pakaian untuk menutup kemaluan laki-laki dalam negara luar Pulau Papua. Koteka terbuat dari Moncong burung taong-taong (Ria...
Australian activist and politician SenatorJacinta Nampijinpa PriceSenator for the Northern TerritoryIncumbentAssumed office 21 May 2022Preceded bySam McMahonDeputy Mayor of Alice SpringsIn office29 September 2020 – 28 August 2021Succeeded byEli MelkyCouncillor for the Town of Alice SpringsIn officeSeptember 2015 – 28 August 2021Preceded byLiz MartinSucceeded byMichael Liddle Personal detailsBornJacinta Yangapi Nampijinpa Price (1981-05-12) 12 May 1981 (age 42)D...
Concours Eurovision de la chanson 1999 Dates Finale 29 mai 1999 Retransmission Lieu International Convention CentreJérusalem, Israël Présentateur(s) Dafna DekelYigal Ravid Sigal Shachmon Superviseur exécutif Christine Marchal-Ortiz Télédiffuseur hôte IBA Ouverture Vues de Jérusalem Entracte Dror Yikrah et Free par Dana International Participants Nombre de participants 23 Débuts Aucun Retour Autriche Bosnie-Herzégovine Danemark Islande Lituanie Relégation Finlande Grèce Macédoine...
Jonesboro, ArkansasKotaCity of Jonesboro Lambang resmi Jonesboro, ArkansasLambangMotto: People, Pride, ProgressLocation of Jonesboro in Craighead County, Arkansas.Lua error in package.lua at line 80: module 'Modul:Location map/data/USA Arkansas' not found.Koordinat: 35°49′41″N 90°41′39″W / 35.82806°N 90.69417°W / 35.82806; -90.69417Koordinat: 35°49′41″N 90°41′39″W / 35.82806°N 90.69417°W / 35.82806; -90.69417Negara...
Sanskrit text on the performing arts Natya ShastraShiva as the Lord of DanceInformationReligionHinduismAuthorBharataLanguageSanskritPart of a series onHindu scriptures and texts Shruti Smriti List Vedas Rigveda Samaveda Yajurveda Atharvaveda Divisions Samhita Brahmana Aranyaka Upanishads UpanishadsRig vedic Aitareya Kaushitaki Sama vedic Chandogya Kena Yajur vedic Brihadaranyaka Isha Taittiriya Katha Shvetashvatara Maitri Atharva vedic Mundaka Mandukya Prashna Other scriptures Agamas Bhagavad...
Untuk orang lain dengan nama yang sama, lihat Richard Russell. Richard Russell Jr. Richard Brevard Russell Jr. (3 November 1897 – 21 Januari 1971) adalah seorang politikus Amerika asal negara bagian Georgia. Seorang anggota Partai Demokrat Amerika Serikat, ia menjabat sebagai Gubernur Georgia sebelum menjabat dalam Senat Amerika Serikat selama hampir 40 tahun, dari 1933 sampai 1971. Russell adalah pendiri dan pemimpin koalisi konservatif yang mendominasi Kongres dari 1937 samp...
Para otros usos de este término, véase Momento de inercia (desambiguación). Una bailarina tendrá más momento de inercia si extiende los brazos, girando más rápido si los contrae. El momento de inercia (símbolo I) es una medida de la inercia rotacional de un cuerpo.[1] Cuando un cuerpo gira en torno a uno de los ejes principales de inercia, la inercia rotacional puede ser representada como una magnitud vectorial llamada momento de inercia. Sin embargo, en el caso más general p...
Village development committee in Bheri Zone, NepalRokayagaun रोकायागाउँVillage development committeeRokayagaunLocation in NepalCoordinates: 29°01′N 82°11′E / 29.02°N 82.18°E / 29.02; 82.18Country NepalZoneBheri ZoneDistrictJajarkot DistrictPopulation (1991) • Total2,364Time zoneUTC+5:45 (Nepal Time) Rokayagaun is a former village development committee in Jajarkot District in the Karnali Province of Nepal. At...
French composer This article needs additional citations for verification. Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources. Unsourced material may be challenged and removed.Find sources: Antoine Brumel – news · newspapers · books · scholar · JSTOR (December 2021) (Learn how and when to remove this message) Antoine Brumel (c. 1460 – 1512 or 1513) was a French composer. He was one of the first renowned French members of the Fran...
1999 film Ride with the DevilTheatrical release posterDirected byAng LeeScreenplay byJames SchamusBased onWoe to Live Onby Daniel WoodrellProduced byTed HopeRobert F. ColesberryJames SchamusStarring Tobey Maguire Skeet Ulrich Jewel Jeffrey Wright Simon Baker Jonathan Rhys Meyers James Caviezel Thomas Guiry Jonathan Brandis CinematographyFrederick ElmesEdited byTim SquyresMusic byMychael DannaProductioncompanyGood MachineDistributed byUSA Films[1]Release dates September 9, 19...
Historic palace in Morocco The courtyard of the main house (photo from 2006)Dar Ba Mohammed Chergui, also known as Dar al-Aman,[1] is a historic palace or riad-style mansion in the old medina of Fez, Morocco. It is located on Derb el Horra street in Fes el-Bali.[2] History and state of preservation The same courtyard in dilapidated condition, late 2022The house was constructed over 15 years in the early 20th century and is named after the former qa'id (judge) Ba Mohammed Cherg...
سيف الدين عزيزي معلومات شخصية الميلاد 12 مارس 1915(1915-03-12)تاتشنغ الوفاة 24 نوفمبر 2003 (88 سنة)بكين مواطنة الصين الاتحاد السوفيتي جمهورية تركستان الشرقية الثانية مناصب الحياة العملية المهنة سياسي الحزب الحزب الشيوعي الصيني، الحزب الشيوعي السوفييتي الخدمة العسكرية تعد�...
Questa voce sull'argomento afrosoricidi è solo un abbozzo. Contribuisci a migliorarla secondo le convenzioni di Wikipedia. Come leggere il tassoboxTalpa dorata del CongoStato di conservazioneDati insufficienti[1] Classificazione scientificaDominioEukaryota RegnoAnimalia PhylumChordata ClasseMammalia SottoclasseTheria InfraclasseEutheria SuperordineAfrotheria OrdineAfrosoricida SottordineChrysochloridea FamigliaChrysochloridae GenereHuetia SpecieH. leucorhina Nomenclatura binomi...
TT Belanda 2019Detail lombaLomba ke 8 dari 19Grand Prix Sepeda Motor musim 2019Tanggal30 Juni 2019Nama resmiMotul TT AssenLokasiTT Circuit Assen, Assen, NetherlandsSirkuitFasilitas balapan permanen4.542 km (2.822 mi)MotoGPPole positionPembalap Fabio Quartararo YamahaCatatan waktu 1:32.017 Putaran tercepatPembalap Marc Márquez HondaCatatan waktu 1:33.712 di lap 4 PodiumPertama Maverick Viñales YamahaKedua Marc Márquez HondaKetiga Fabio Quartararo YamahaMoto2Pole positi...
American sportscaster (1923–2005) Chris SchenkelSchenkel in 1964Born(1923-08-21)August 21, 1923Bippus, Indiana, U.S.DiedSeptember 11, 2005(2005-09-11) (aged 82)Fort Wayne, Indiana, U.S.OccupationSportscasterYears active1947−1997Spouse Fran Paige (m. 1955)Children3 Christopher Eugene Schenkel (August 21, 1923 – September 11, 2005) was an American sportscaster. Over the course of five decades he called play-by-play for numerous sports on televisio...
Species of mammal Günther's dik-dik Günther's dik-dik at Samburu National Reserve, Kenya Conservation status Least Concern (IUCN 3.1)[1] Scientific classification Domain: Eukaryota Kingdom: Animalia Phylum: Chordata Class: Mammalia Order: Artiodactyla Family: Bovidae Subfamily: Antilopinae Genus: Madoqua Species: M. guentheri Binomial name Madoqua guentheriThomas, 1894[2] The range of Günther's dik-dik Günther's dik-dik (Madoqua guentheri) is a small antelope fo...
Римская армиялат. classisлат. exercitus Вексиллум с императорской аквилой Годы существования 753 до н. э. — 476 н. э. Страна Римское царство Римская республика Римская империя Входит в вооружённые силы Древнего Рима[вд] Включает в себя Римские легионы Численность 28-50 легионо...