The word probability has been used in a variety of ways since it was first applied to the mathematical study of games of chance. Does probability measure the real, physical, tendency of something to occur, or is it a measure of how strongly one believes it will occur, or does it draw on both these elements? In answering such questions, mathematicians interpret the probability values of probability theory.
There are two broad categories[1][2] of probability interpretations which can be called "physical" and "evidential" probabilities. Physical probabilities, which are also called objective or frequency probabilities, are associated with random physical systems such as roulette wheels, rolling dice and radioactive atoms. In such systems, a given type of event (such as a die yielding a six) tends to occur at a persistent rate, or "relative frequency", in a long run of trials. Physical probabilities either explain, or are invoked to explain, these stable frequencies. The two main kinds of theory of physical probability are frequentist accounts (such as those of Venn,[3] Reichenbach[4] and von Mises)[5] and propensity accounts (such as those of Popper, Miller, Giere and Fetzer).[6]
Evidential probability, also called Bayesian probability, can be assigned to any statement whatsoever, even when no random process is involved, as a way to represent its subjective plausibility, or the degree to which the statement is supported by the available evidence. On most accounts, evidential probabilities are considered to be degrees of belief, defined in terms of dispositions to gamble at certain odds. The four main evidential interpretations are the classical (e.g. Laplace's)[7] interpretation, the subjective interpretation (de Finetti[8] and Savage),[9] the epistemic or inductive interpretation (Ramsey,[10]Cox)[11] and the logical interpretation (Keynes[12] and Carnap).[13] There are also evidential interpretations of probability covering groups, which are often labelled as 'intersubjective' (proposed by Gillies[14] and Rowbottom).[6]
Some interpretations of probability are associated with approaches to statistical inference, including theories of estimation and hypothesis testing. The physical interpretation, for example, is taken by followers of "frequentist" statistical methods, such as Ronald Fisher[dubious – discuss], Jerzy Neyman and Egon Pearson. Statisticians of the opposing Bayesian school typically accept the frequency interpretation when it makes sense (although not as a definition), but there is less agreement regarding physical probabilities. Bayesians consider the calculation of evidential probabilities to be both valid and necessary in statistics. This article, however, focuses on the interpretations of probability rather than theories of statistical inference.
The terminology of this topic is rather confusing, in part because probabilities are studied within a variety of academic fields. The word "frequentist" is especially tricky. To philosophers it refers to a particular theory of physical probability, one that has more or less been abandoned. To scientists, on the other hand, "frequentist probability" is just another name for physical (or objective) probability. Those who promote Bayesian inference view "frequentist statistics" as an approach to statistical inference that is based on the frequency interpretation of probability, usually relying on the law of large numbers and characterized by what is called 'Null Hypothesis Significance Testing' (NHST). Also the word "objective", as applied to probability, sometimes means exactly what "physical" means here, but is also used of evidential probabilities that are fixed by rational constraints, such as logical and epistemic probabilities.
It is unanimously agreed that statistics depends somehow on probability. But, as to what probability is and how it is connected with statistics, there has seldom been such complete disagreement and breakdown of communication since the Tower of Babel. Doubtless, much of the disagreement is merely terminological and would disappear under sufficiently sharp analysis.
The philosophy of probability presents problems chiefly in matters of epistemology and the uneasy interface between mathematical concepts and ordinary language as it is used by non-mathematicians.
Probability theory is an established field of study in mathematics. It has its origins in correspondence discussing the mathematics of games of chance between Blaise Pascal and Pierre de Fermat in the seventeenth century,[15] and was formalized and rendered axiomatic as a distinct branch of mathematics by Andrey Kolmogorov in the twentieth century. In axiomatic form, mathematical statements about probability theory carry the same sort of epistemological confidence within the philosophy of mathematics as are shared by other mathematical statements.[16][17]
The mathematical analysis originated in observations of the behaviour of game equipment such as playing cards and dice, which are designed specifically to introduce random and equalized elements; in mathematical terms, they are subjects of indifference. This is not the only way probabilistic statements are used in ordinary human language: when people say that "it will probably rain", they typically do not mean that the outcome of rain versus not-rain is a random factor that the odds currently favor; instead, such statements are perhaps better understood as qualifying their expectation of rain with a degree of confidence. Likewise, when it is written that "the most probable explanation" of the name of Ludlow, Massachusetts "is that it was named after Roger Ludlow", what is meant here is not that Roger Ludlow is favored by a random factor, but rather that this is the most plausible explanation of the evidence, which admits other, less likely explanations.
Thomas Bayes attempted to provide a logic that could handle varying degrees of confidence; as such, Bayesian probability is an attempt to recast the representation of probabilistic statements as an expression of the degree of confidence by which the beliefs they express are held.
The first attempt at mathematical rigour in the field of probability, championed by Pierre-Simon Laplace, is now known as the classical definition. Developed from studies of games of chance (such as rolling dice) it states that probability is shared equally between all the possible outcomes, provided these outcomes can be deemed equally likely.[1] (3.1)
The theory of chance consists in reducing all the events of the same kind to a certain number of cases equally possible, that is to say, to such as we may be equally undecided about in regard to their existence, and in determining the number of cases favorable to the event whose probability is sought. The ratio of this number to that of all the cases possible is the measure of this probability, which is thus simply a fraction whose numerator is the number of favorable cases and whose denominator is the number of all the cases possible.
— Pierre-Simon Laplace, A Philosophical Essay on Probabilities[7]
This can be represented mathematically as follows:
If a random experiment can result in N mutually exclusive and equally likely outcomes and if NA of these outcomes result in the occurrence of the event A, the probability of A is defined by
There are two clear limitations to the classical definition.[18] Firstly, it is applicable only to situations in which there is only a 'finite' number of possible outcomes. But some important random experiments, such as tossing a coin until it shows heads, give rise to an infinite set of outcomes. And secondly, it requires an a priori determination that all possible outcomes are equally likely without falling in a trap of circular reasoning by relying on the notion of probability. (In using the terminology "we may be equally undecided", Laplace assumed, by what has been called the "principle of insufficient reason", that all possible outcomes are equally likely if there is no known reason to assume otherwise, for which there is no obvious justification.[19][20])
Frequentists posit that the probability of an event is its relative frequency over time,[1] (3.4) i.e., its relative frequency of occurrence after repeating a process a large number of times under similar conditions. This is also known as aleatory probability. The events are assumed to be governed by some random physical phenomena, which are either phenomena that are predictable, in principle, with sufficient information (see determinism); or phenomena which are essentially unpredictable. Examples of the first kind include tossing dice or spinning a roulette wheel; an example of the second kind is radioactive decay. In the case of tossing a fair coin, frequentists say that the probability of getting a heads is 1/2, not because there are two equally likely outcomes but because repeated series of large numbers of trials demonstrate that the empirical frequency converges to the limit 1/2 as the number of trials goes to infinity.
If we denote by the number of occurrences of an event in trials, then if we say that .
The frequentist view has its own problems. It is of course impossible to actually perform an infinity of repetitions of a random experiment to determine the probability of an event. But if only a finite number of repetitions of the process are performed, different relative frequencies will appear in different series of trials. If these relative frequencies are to define the probability, the probability will be slightly different every time it is measured. But the real probability should be the same every time. If we acknowledge the fact that we only can measure a probability with some error of measurement attached, we still get into problems as the error of measurement can only be expressed as a probability, the very concept we are trying to define. This renders even the frequency definition circular; see for example “What is the Chance of an Earthquake?”[21]
Subjectivists, also known as Bayesians or followers of epistemic probability, give the notion of probability a subjective status by regarding it as a measure of the 'degree of belief' of the individual assessing the uncertainty of a particular situation. Epistemic or subjective probability is sometimes called credence, as opposed to the term chance for a propensity probability. Some examples of epistemic probability are to assign a probability to the proposition that a proposed law of physics is true or to determine how probable it is that a suspect committed a crime, based on the evidence presented. The use of Bayesian probability raises the philosophical debate as to whether it can contribute valid justifications of belief. Bayesians point to the work of Ramsey[10] (p 182) and de Finetti[8] (p 103) as proving that subjective beliefs must follow the laws of probability if they are to be coherent.[22] Evidence casts doubt that humans will have coherent beliefs.[23][24] The use of Bayesian probability involves specifying a prior probability. This may be obtained from consideration of whether the required prior probability is greater or lesser than a reference probability[clarification needed] associated with an urn model or a thought experiment. The issue is that for a given problem, multiple thought experiments could apply, and choosing one is a matter of judgement: different people may assign different prior probabilities, known as the reference class problem. The "sunrise problem" provides an example.
Propensity theorists think of probability as a physical propensity, or disposition, or tendency of a given type of physical situation to yield an outcome of a certain kind or to yield a long run relative frequency of such an outcome.[25] This kind of objective probability is sometimes called 'chance'.
Propensities, or chances, are not relative frequencies, but purported causes of the observed stable relative frequencies. Propensities are invoked to explain why repeating a certain kind of experiment will generate given outcome types at persistent rates, which are known as propensities or chances. Frequentists are unable to take this approach, since relative frequencies do not exist for single tosses of a coin, but only for large ensembles or collectives (see "single case possible" in the table above).[2] In contrast, a propensitist is able to use the law of large numbers to explain the behaviour of long-run frequencies. This law, which is a consequence of the axioms of probability, says that if (for example) a coin is tossed repeatedly many times, in such a way that its probability of landing heads is the same on each toss, and the outcomes are probabilistically independent, then the relative frequency of heads will be close to the probability of heads on each single toss. This law allows that stable long-run frequencies are a manifestation of invariant single-case probabilities. In addition to explaining the emergence of stable relative frequencies, the idea of propensity is motivated by the desire to make sense of single-case probability attributions in quantum mechanics, such as the probability of decay of a particular atom at a particular time.
The main challenge facing propensity theories is to say exactly what propensity means. (And then, of course, to show that propensity thus defined has the required properties.) At present, unfortunately, none of the well-recognised accounts of propensity comes close to meeting this challenge.
A propensity theory of probability was given by Charles Sanders Peirce.[26][27][28][29] A later propensity theory was proposed by philosopher Karl Popper, who had only slight acquaintance with the writings of C. S. Peirce, however.[26][27] Popper noted that the outcome of a physical experiment is produced by a certain set of "generating conditions". When we repeat an experiment, as the saying goes, we really perform another experiment with a (more or less) similar set of generating conditions. To say that a set of generating conditions has propensity p of producing the outcome E means that those exact conditions, if repeated indefinitely, would produce an outcome sequence in which E occurred with limiting relative frequency p. For Popper then, a deterministic experiment would have propensity 0 or 1 for each outcome, since those generating conditions would have same outcome on each trial. In other words, non-trivial propensities (those that differ from 0 and 1) only exist for genuinely nondeterministic experiments.
A number of other philosophers, including David Miller and Donald A. Gillies, have proposed propensity theories somewhat similar to Popper's.
Other propensity theorists (e.g. Ronald Giere[30]) do not explicitly define propensities at all, but rather see propensity as defined by the theoretical role it plays in science. They argued, for example, that physical magnitudes such as electrical charge cannot be explicitly defined either, in terms of more basic things, but only in terms of what they do (such as attracting and repelling other electrical charges). In a similar way, propensity is whatever fills the various roles that physical probability plays in science.
What roles does physical probability play in science? What are its properties? One central property of chance is that, when known, it constrains rational belief to take the same numerical value. David Lewis called this the Principal Principle,[1] (3.3 & 3.5) a term that philosophers have mostly adopted. For example, suppose you are certain that a particular biased coin has propensity 0.32 to land heads every time it is tossed. What is then the correct price for a gamble that pays $1 if the coin lands heads, and nothing otherwise? According to the Principal Principle, the fair price is 32 cents.
It is widely recognized that the term "probability" is sometimes used in contexts where it has nothing to do with physical randomness. Consider, for example, the claim that the extinction of the dinosaurs was probably caused by a large meteorite hitting the earth. Statements such as "Hypothesis H is probably true" have been interpreted to mean that the (presently available) empirical evidence (E, say) supports H to a high degree. This degree of support of H by E has been called the logical, or epistemic, or inductive probability of H given E.
The differences between these interpretations are rather small, and may seem inconsequential. One of the main points of disagreement lies in the relation between probability and belief. Logical probabilities are conceived (for example in Keynes' Treatise on Probability[12]) to be objective, logical relations between propositions (or sentences), and hence not to depend in any way upon belief. They are degrees of (partial) entailment, or degrees of logical consequence, not degrees of belief. (They do, nevertheless, dictate proper degrees of belief, as is discussed below.) Frank P. Ramsey, on the other hand, was skeptical about the existence of such objective logical relations and argued that (evidential) probability is "the logic of partial belief".[10] (p 157) In other words, Ramsey held that epistemic probabilities simply are degrees of rational belief, rather than being logical relations that merely constrain degrees of rational belief.
Another point of disagreement concerns the uniqueness of evidential probability, relative to a given state of knowledge. Rudolf Carnap held, for example, that logical principles always determine a unique logical probability for any statement, relative to any body of evidence. Ramsey, by contrast, thought that while degrees of belief are subject to some rational constraints (such as, but not limited to, the axioms of probability) these constraints usually do not determine a unique value. Rational people, in other words, may differ somewhat in their degrees of belief, even if they all have the same information.
An alternative account of probability emphasizes the role of prediction – predicting future observations on the basis of past observations, not on unobservable parameters. In its modern form, it is mainly in the Bayesian vein. This was the main function of probability before the 20th century,[31] but fell out of favor compared to the parametric approach, which modeled phenomena as a physical system that was observed with error, such as in celestial mechanics.
The modern predictive approach was pioneered by Bruno de Finetti, with the central idea of exchangeability – that future observations should behave like past observations.[31] This view came to the attention of the Anglophone world with the 1974 translation of de Finetti's book,[31] and has
since been propounded by such statisticians as Seymour Geisser.
Axiomatic probability
The mathematics of probability can be developed on an entirely axiomatic basis that is independent of any interpretation: see the articles on probability theory and probability axioms for a detailed treatment.
^ abcdHájek, Alan (21 October 2002), Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), Interpretations of Probability, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy The taxonomy of probability interpretations given here is similar to that of the longer and more complete Interpretations of Probability article in the online Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. References to that article include a parenthetic section number where appropriate. A partial outline of that article:
Section 2: Criteria of adequacy for the interpretations of probability
Section 3:
3.1 Classical Probability
3.2 Logical Probability
3.3 Subjective Probability
3.4 Frequency Interpretations
3.5 Propensity Interpretations
^ abcde Elía, Ramón; Laprise, René (2005). "Diversity in interpretations of probability: implications for weather forecasting". Monthly Weather Review. 133 (5): 1129–1143. Bibcode:2005MWRv..133.1129D. doi:10.1175/mwr2913.1. S2CID123135127.
"There are several schools of thought regarding the interpretation of probabilities, none of them without flaws, internal contradictions, or paradoxes." (p 1129)
"There are no standard classifications of probability interpretations, and even the more popular ones may suffer subtle variations from text to text." (p 1130)
The classification in this article is representative, as are the authors and ideas claimed for each classification.
^Reichenbach, Hans (1948). The theory of probability, an inquiry into the logical and mathematical foundations of the calculus of probability. University of California Press. English translation of the original 1935 German. ASIN: B000R0D5MS
^Mises, Richard (1981). Probability, statistics, and truth. New York: Dover Publications. ISBN978-0-486-24214-9. English translation of the third German edition of 1951 which was published 30 years after the first German edition.
^ abLaplace, P. S., 1814, English edition 1951, A Philosophical Essay on Probabilities, New York: Dover Publications Inc.
^ abde Finetti, Bruno (1964). "Foresight: its Logical laws, its Subjective Sources". In Kyburg, H. E. (ed.). Studies in Subjective Probability. H. E. Smokler. New York: Wiley. pp. 93–158. Translation of the 1937 French original with later notes added.
^ abcRamsey, F. P. (1931). "Chapter VII, Truth and Probability (1926)"(PDF). In Braithwaite, R. B. (ed.). Foundations of Mathematics and Other Logical Essays. London: Kegan, Paul, Trench, Trubner & Co. pp. 156–198. Retrieved 15 August 2013. Contains three chapters (essays) by Ramsey. The electronic version contains only those three.
^Cox, Richard Threlkeld (1961). The algebra of probable inference. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins Press.
^Carnap, Rudolph (1950). Logical Foundations of Probability. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Carnap coined the notion "probability1" and "probability2" for evidential and physical probability, respectively.
^Laszlo E. Szabo, Objective probability-like things with and without objective indeterminism, Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 38 (2007) 626–634 (Preprint)
^Spanos, Aris (1986). Statistical foundations of econometric modelling. Cambridge New York: Cambridge University Press. ISBN978-0521269124.
^Freedman, David and Philip B. Stark (2003)"What is the Chance of an Earthquake?" Earthquake Science and Seismic Risk.
^Jaynes, E. T. (2003). Probability theory the logic of science. Cambridge, UK New York, NY: Cambridge University Press. ISBN978-0521592710.
^Kahneman, Daniel (2011). Thinking, fast and slow. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux. ISBN978-0374275631. The book contains numerous examples of the difference between idealized and actual thought. "[W]hen called upon to judge probability, people actually judge something else and believe they have judged probability." (p 98)
Eagle, Antony (2011). Philosophy of probability : contemporary readings. Abingdon, Oxon New York: Routledge. ISBN978-0415483872.
Gillies, Donald (2000). Philosophical theories of probability. London New York: Routledge. ISBN978-0415182768. A comprehensive monograph covering the four principal current interpretations: logical, subjective, frequency, propensity. Also proposes a novel intersubective interpretation.
Hacking, Ian (2006). The emergence of probability : a philosophical study of early ideas about probability, induction and statistical inference. Cambridge New York: Cambridge University Press. ISBN978-0521685573.
Vol. 2: Philosophy of Physics, Theory Structure and Measurement, and Action Theory.
Jackson, Frank, and Robert Pargetter (1982) "Physical Probability as a Propensity," Noûs 16(4): 567–583.
Khrennikov, Andrei (2009). Interpretations of probability (2nd ed.). Berlin New York: Walter de Gruyter. ISBN978-3110207484. Covers mostly non-Kolmogorov probability models, particularly with respect to quantum physics.
Plato, Jan von (1994). Creating modern probability : its mathematics, physics, and philosophy in historical perspective. Cambridge England New York: Cambridge University Press. ISBN978-0521597357.
Rowbottom, Darrell (2015). Probability. Cambridge: Polity. ISBN978-0745652573. A highly accessible introduction to the interpretation of probability. Covers all the main interpretations, and proposes a novel group level (or 'intersubjective') interpretation. Also covers fallacies and applications of interpretations in the social and natural sciences.
Skyrms, Brian (2000). Choice and chance : an introduction to inductive logic. Australia Belmont, CA: Wadsworth/Thomson Learning. ISBN978-0534557379.
This article is an orphan, as no other articles link to it. Please introduce links to this page from related articles; try the Find link tool for suggestions. (September 2023) Bahdinan prisoners is used to refer to the arrest of a group of four journalists and an activist in the Bahdinan area of Kurdistan Region. The term only became used when the group were convicted of spying[1] by the KDP on 16 February 2021. The term was used by the speaker of parliament Rewaz Faeq to refer to the...
العلاقات الساموية الغيانية ساموا غيانا ساموا غيانا تعديل مصدري - تعديل العلاقات الساموية الغيانية هي العلاقات الثنائية التي تجمع بين ساموا وغيانا.[1][2][3][4][5] مقارنة بين البلدين هذه مقارنة عامة ومرجعية للدولتين: وجه المقارنة ساموا غيان...
Referendum in Colorado Proposition FFReduce Income Tax Deduction Amounts to Fund School Meals Program MeasureResults Choice Votes % Yes 1,384,852 56.75% No 1,055,583 43.25% Valid votes 2,440,435 100.00% Invalid or blank votes 0 0.00% Total votes 2,440,435 100.00% Registered voters/turnout 3,833,468 63.66% County results Precinct results For 80–90% 70–80% 60–70% 50–60% Against 90–100% 80–90% 70–80...
Narrative poem by Øyvind Rimbereid Solaris korrigert (Solaris Corrected)by Øyvind RimbereidCover of the 1st edition.Original titleSolaris korrigertWritten2004CountryNorwayLanguageA fictional future language based on Norwegian (Stavanger dialect) with English, German and old Norse mixed inSubject(s)Science fictionFormNarrativePublisherGyldendal Norsk ForlagPublication date2004Media typePrintISBN9788205332355OCLC1028421725 Solaris korrigert is a Norwegian narrative poem by Øyvind Rimbereid, ...
Sporting event delegationTurkey at the2010 Winter OlympicsIOC codeTURNOCTurkish National Olympic CommitteeWebsiteolimpiyat.org.tr (in English and Turkish)in VancouverCompetitors5 in 3 sportsFlag bearer Kelime ÇetinkayaMedals Gold 0 Silver 0 Bronze 0 Total 0 Winter Olympics appearances (overview)193619481952195619601964196819721976198019841988199219941998200220062010201420182022 Turkey participated at the 2010 Winter Olympics in Vancouver, British Columbia, Canada. Competitors Sport...
artikel ini perlu dirapikan agar memenuhi standar Wikipedia. Tidak ada alasan yang diberikan. Silakan kembangkan artikel ini semampu Anda. Merapikan artikel dapat dilakukan dengan wikifikasi atau membagi artikel ke paragraf-paragraf. Jika sudah dirapikan, silakan hapus templat ini. (Pelajari cara dan kapan saatnya untuk menghapus pesan templat ini) Artikel ini tidak memiliki referensi atau sumber tepercaya sehingga isinya tidak bisa dipastikan. Tolong bantu perbaiki artikel ini dengan menamba...
Disambiguazione – Se stai cercando la serie animata, vedi Harlem Globetrotters (serie animata). Harlem GlobetrottersPallacanestro Segni distintivi Uniformi di gara Casa Trasferta Colori sociali Rosso, bianco e blu Inno Sweet Georgia BrownKenneth Casey Dati societari Città Peachtree City Nazione Stati Uniti Fondazione 1926 Proprietario Herschend Family Allenatore Lou Dunbar Impianto Variabile Sito web www.harle...
For the Super Nintendo Entertainment System game, see Super Tennis. 1985 video gameSuper TennisDeveloper(s)SegaPublisher(s)SegaPlatform(s)Master SystemReleaseJP: 22 December 1985[1]NA: December 1986[3]EU: August 1987[2]Genre(s)SportsMode(s)Up to 2 players, cooperative Super Tennis is a tennis video game developed and published by Sega for the Master System. It was known in Japan as Great Tennis (グレートテニス). It was released as a Sega Card, and additionally a...
Pour les articles homonymes, voir Bonelli. Cesare Bonelli Fonctions Ministre de la Guerre du royaume d'Italie 24 octobre 1878 – 19 décembre 1878(1 mois et 25 jours) Monarque Humbert Ier (roi d'Italie) Gouvernement Benedetto Cairoli Législature XIIIe Prédécesseur Giovanni Bruzzo Successeur Gustavo Mazè de la Roche 14 juillet 1879 – 13 juillet 1880(11 mois et 29 jours) Législature XIIIe et XIVe Prédécesseur Gustavo Mazè de la Roche Successeur Ferdinando Acton M...
Questa voce sull'argomento stagioni delle società calcistiche italiane è solo un abbozzo. Contribuisci a migliorarla secondo le convenzioni di Wikipedia. Segui i suggerimenti del progetto di riferimento. Voce principale: Associazione Calcio Asti. Unione Sportiva Asti Sezione CalcioStagione 1942-1943Sport calcio Squadra Asti Allenatore Filippo Pascucci Presidente Pietro Salvaneschi Serie Cescluso 1941-1942 1943-1944 Si invita a seguire il modello di voce Questa voce raccoglie le i...
Artikel ini sebatang kara, artinya tidak ada artikel lain yang memiliki pranala balik ke halaman ini.Bantulah menambah pranala ke artikel ini dari artikel yang berhubungan atau coba peralatan pencari pranala.Tag ini diberikan pada September 2016. Robbie BlakeInformasi pribadiNama lengkap Robert James BlakeTanggal lahir 4 Maret 1976 (umur 48)Tempat lahir Middlesbrough, InggrisTinggi 5 ft 9 in (1,75 m)Posisi bermain PenyerangKarier senior*Tahun Tim Tampil (Gol)1994–1997 Da...
Overview of crime in Bangladesh Bangladeshi police car. Crime in Bangladesh is present in various forms such as drug trafficking, money laundering, extortion, contract killing, fraud, human trafficking, robbery, corruption, black marketeering, political violence, terrorism and abduction, wildlife trafficking, among others. Narcotics trafficking Bangladesh is used as a transit route for narcotics produced in neighboring countries.[1] The Annual Report for 2007 from the International Na...
Đài Phát thanh – Truyền hình Kon TumQuốc gia Việt NamKhu vựcphát sóng Việt NamTrụ sởSố 258A, Phan Đình Phùng, TP Kon TumChương trìnhNgôn ngữTiếng Việt, Tiếng Xê Đăng, Tiếng Ba Na, Tiếng Giẻ, Tiếng Triêng, Tiếng Gia RaiĐịnh dạng hình1080i HDTVSở hữuChủ sở hữuỦy ban Nhân dân tỉnh Kon TumLịch sửLên sóng30 tháng 11 năm 1991; 32 năm trước (1991-11-30)Liên kết ngoàiW...
American corporation This article's lead section may be too short to adequately summarize the key points. Please consider expanding the lead to provide an accessible overview of all important aspects of the article. (February 2021) Brunswick CorporationCompany typePublicTraded asNYSE: BCS&P 400 componentIndustryRecreational MarineFoundedCincinnati, OhioSeptember 15, 1845; 178 years ago (1845-09-15)FounderJohn Moses BrunswickHeadquartersMettawa, Illinois, U.S.[1&...
Bay on the Texas coast, United States of America Matagorda BayMatagorda BayMatagorda Bay at Jensen PointLocationCentral Texas Gulf CoastCoordinates28°33′56″N 96°12′36″W / 28.56556°N 96.21000°W / 28.56556; -96.21000River sourcesColorado River (Texas), Lavaca RiverOcean/sea sourcesGulf of MexicoBasin countriesUnited StatesSurface area244,490 acres (98,940 ha)[1]SettlementsPort Lavaca, Texas Matagorda Bay (/ˌmætəˈɡɔːrdə/ ⓘ[2...
Habitat for communities made up of populations of multiple species Amazon rain forest biotope A biotope is an area of uniform environmental conditions providing a living place for a specific assemblage of plants and animals. Biotope is almost synonymous with the term habitat, which is more commonly used in English-speaking countries. However, in some countries these two terms are distinguished: the subject of a habitat is a population, the subject of a biotope is a biocoenosis or biological c...
Questa voce o sezione sull'argomento Stagioni delle società calcistiche non è ancora formattata secondo gli standard. Commento: si invita a seguire il modello di voce Contribuisci a migliorarla secondo le convenzioni di Wikipedia. Segui i suggerimenti del progetto di riferimento. Voce principale: Sporting Club de Bastia. Sporting Club de BastiaStagione 2007-2008Sport calcio Squadra Bastia AllenatoreBernard Casoni PresidenteCharles Orlanducci Ligue 211º Coppa di FranciaOttavi di ...
Sweden-held lands on the southern Baltic coast (1630–1815) Swedish PomeraniaSvenska Pommern (Swedish)Schwedisch-Pommern (German)1630–1815 Flag of Sweden Coat of arms(1660) Swedish Pomerania (orange) within the Swedish Empire in 1658StatusSwedish DominionState of the Holy Roman Empire until 1806CapitalStettin(Szczecin, 1630–1720)Stralsund(1720–1815)Common languagesLow GermanGermanSwedishReligion LutheranismGovernmentPrincipalityDuke • 1630–1632 Gustav II Ad...