Noumenon

In philosophy, a noumenon (/ˈnmənɒn/, /ˈn-/; from Greek: νοούμενoν; pl.: noumena) is knowledge[1] posited as an object that exists independently of human sense.[2] The term noumenon is generally used in contrast with, or in relation to, the term phenomenon, which refers to any object of the senses. Immanuel Kant first developed the notion of the noumenon as part of his transcendental idealism, suggesting that while we know the noumenal world to exist because human sensibility is merely receptive, it is not itself sensible and must therefore remain otherwise unknowable to us.[3] In Kantian philosophy, the noumenon is often associated with the unknowable "thing-in-itself" (German: Ding an sich). However, the nature of the relationship between the two is not made explicit in Kant's work, and remains a subject of debate among Kant scholars as a result.

Etymology

The Greek word νοούμενoν, nooúmenon (plural νοούμενα, nooúmena) is the neuter middle-passive present participle of νοεῖν, noeîn, 'to think, to mean', which in turn originates from the word νοῦς, noûs, an Attic contracted form of νόος, nóos, 'perception, understanding, mind'.[a][4][5] A rough equivalent in English would be "that which is thought", or "the object of an act of thought".

Historical predecessors

The Indian Vedānta philosophy (specifically Advaita), the roots of which go back to the Vedic period, talks of the ātman (self) in similar terms as the noumenon.

[6] Regarding the equivalent concepts in Plato, Ted Honderich writes: "Platonic Ideas and Forms are noumena, and phenomena are things displaying themselves to the senses... This dichotomy is the most characteristic feature of Plato's dualism; that noumena and the noumenal world are objects of the highest knowledge, truths, and values is Plato's principal legacy to philosophy."[7]

Kantian noumena

Overview

As expressed in Kant's Critique of Pure Reason, human understanding is structured by "concepts of the understanding" or pure categories of understanding, found prior to experience in the mind and which make outer experiences possible as counterpart to the rational faculties of the mind.[8][9]

By Kant's account, when one employs a concept to describe or categorize noumena (the objects of inquiry, investigation or analysis of the workings of the world), one is also employing a way of describing or categorizing phenomena (the observable manifestations of those objects of inquiry, investigation or analysis). Kant posited methods by which human understanding makes sense of and thus intuits phenomena that appear to the mind: the concepts of the transcendental aesthetic, as well as that of the transcendental analytic, transcendental logic and transcendental deduction.[10][11][12] Taken together, Kant's "categories of understanding" are the principles of the human mind which necessarily are brought to bear in attempting to understand the world in which we exist (that is, to understand, or attempt to understand, "things in themselves"). In each instance the word "transcendental" refers to the process that the human mind must exercise to understand or grasp the form of, and order among, phenomena. Kant asserts that to "transcend" a direct observation or experience is to use reason and classifications to strive to correlate with the phenomena that are observed.[citation needed] Humans can make sense out of phenomena in these various ways, but in doing so can never know the "things-in-themselves", the actual objects and dynamics of the natural world in their noumenal dimension - this being the negative, correlate to phenomena and that which escapes the limits of human understanding. By Kant's Critique, our minds may attempt to correlate in useful ways, perhaps even closely accurate ways, with the structure and order of the various aspects of the universe, but cannot know these "things-in-themselves" (noumena) directly. Rather, we must infer the extent to which the human rational faculties can reach the object of "things-in-themselves" by our observations of the manifestations of those things that can be perceived via the physical senses, that is, of phenomena, and by ordering these perceptions in the mind help infer the validity of our perceptions to the rational categories used to understand them in a rational system. This rational system (transcendental analytic), being the categories of the understanding as free from empirical contingency.[13][14]

According to Kant, objects of which we are cognizant via the physical senses are merely representations of unknown somethings—what Kant refers to as the transcendental object—as interpreted through the a priori or categories of the understanding. These unknown somethings are manifested within the noumenon—although we can never know how or why as our perceptions of these unknown somethings via our physical senses are bound by the limitations of the categories of the understanding and we are therefore never able to fully know the "thing-in-itself".[15]

Noumenon and the thing-in-itself

Many accounts of Kant's philosophy treat "noumenon" and "thing-in-itself" as synonymous, and there is textual evidence for this relationship.[16] However, Stephen Palmquist holds that "noumenon" and "thing-in-itself" are only loosely synonymous, inasmuch as they represent the same concept viewed from two different perspectives,[17][18] and other scholars also argue that they are not identical.[19] Schopenhauer criticised Kant for changing the meaning of "noumenon". However, this opinion is far from unanimous.[20] Kant's writings show points of difference between noumena and things-in-themselves. For instance, he regards things-in-themselves as existing:

...though we cannot know these objects as things in themselves, we must yet be in a position at least to think them as things in themselves; otherwise we should be landed in the absurd conclusion that there can be appearance without anything that appears.[21]

He is much more doubtful about noumena:

But in that case a noumenon is not for our understanding a special [kind of] object, namely, an intelligible object; the [sort of] understanding to which it might belong is itself a problem. For we cannot in the least represent to ourselves the possibility of an understanding which should know its object, not discursively through categories, but intuitively in a non-sensible intuition.[22]

A crucial difference between the noumenon and the thing-in-itself is that to call something a noumenon is to claim a kind of knowledge, whereas Kant insisted that the thing-in-itself is unknowable. Interpreters have debated whether the latter claim makes sense: it seems to imply that we know at least one thing about the thing-in-itself (i.e., that it is unknowable). But Stephen Palmquist explains that this is part of Kant's definition of the term, to the extent that anyone who claims to have found a way of making the thing-in-itself knowable must be adopting a non-Kantian position.[23]

Positive and negative noumena

Kant also makes a distinction between positive and negative noumena:[24][25]

If by 'noumenon' we mean a thing so far as it is not an object of our sensible intuition, and so abstract from our mode of intuiting it, this is a noumenon in the negative sense of the term.[26]

But if we understand by it an object of a non-sensible intuition, we thereby presuppose a special mode of intuition, namely, the intellectual, which is not that which we possess, and of which we cannot comprehend even the possibility. This would be 'noumenon' in the positive sense of the term.[26]

The positive noumena, if they existed, would be immaterial entities that can only be apprehended by a special, non-sensory faculty: "intellectual intuition" (nicht sinnliche Anschauung).[26] Kant doubts that we have such a faculty, because for him intellectual intuition would mean that thinking of an entity, and its being represented, would be the same. He argues that humans have no way to apprehend positive noumena:

Since, however, such a type of intuition, intellectual intuition, forms no part whatsoever of our faculty of knowledge, it follows that the employment of the categories can never extend further than to the objects of experience. Doubtless, indeed, there are intelligible entities corresponding to the sensible entities; there may also be intelligible entities to which our sensible faculty of intuition has no relation whatsoever; but our concepts of understanding, being mere forms of thought for our sensible intuition, could not in the least apply to them. That, therefore, which we entitle 'noumenon' must be understood as being such only in a negative sense.[27]

The noumenon as a limiting concept

Even if noumena are unknowable, they are still needed as a limiting concept,[28] Kant tells us. Without them, there would be only phenomena, and since potentially we have complete knowledge of our phenomena, we would in a sense know everything. In his own words:

Further, the concept of a noumenon is necessary, to prevent sensible intuition from being extended to things in themselves, and thus to limit the objective validity of sensible knowledge.[29]

What our understanding acquires through this concept of a noumenon, is a negative extension; that is to say, understanding is not limited through sensibility; on the contrary, it itself limits sensibility by applying the term noumena to things in themselves (things not regarded as appearances). But in so doing it at the same time sets limits to itself, recognising that it cannot know these noumena through any of the categories, and that it must therefore think them only under the title of an unknown something.[30]

Furthermore, for Kant, the existence of a noumenal world limits reason to what he perceives to be its proper bounds, making many questions of traditional metaphysics, such as the existence of God, the soul, and free will unanswerable by reason. Kant derives this from his definition of knowledge as "the determination of given representations to an object".[31] As there are no appearances of these entities in the phenomenal, Kant is able to make the claim that they cannot be known to a mind that works upon "such knowledge that has to do only with appearances".[32] These questions are ultimately the "proper object of faith, but not of reason".[33]

The dual-object and dual-aspect interpretations

Kantian scholars have long debated two contrasting interpretations of the thing-in-itself. One is the dual object view, according to which the thing-in-itself is an entity distinct from the phenomena to which it gives rise. The other is the dual aspect view, according to which the thing-in-itself and the thing-as-it-appears are two "sides" of the same thing. This view is supported by the textual fact that "Most occurrences of the phrase 'things-in-themselves' are shorthand for the phrase, 'things considered in themselves' (Dinge an sich selbst betrachtet)."[34] Although we cannot see things apart from the way we do in fact perceive them via the physical senses, we can think them apart from our mode of sensibility (physical perception); thus making the thing-in-itself a kind of noumenon or object of thought.

Criticisms of Kant's noumenon

Pre-Kantian critique

Though the term noumenon did not come into common usage until Kant, the idea that undergirds it, that matter has an absolute existence which causes it to emanate certain phenomena, had historically been subjected to criticism. George Berkeley, who pre-dated Kant, asserted that matter, independent of an observant mind, is metaphysically impossible. Qualities associated with matter, such as shape, color, smell, texture, weight, temperature, and sound are all dependent on minds, which allow only for relative perception, not absolute perception. The complete absence of such minds (and more importantly an omnipotent mind) would render those same qualities unobservable and even unimaginable. Berkeley called this philosophy immaterialism. Essentially there could be no such thing as matter without a mind.[35]

Schopenhauer's critique

Schopenhauer claimed that Kant used the word noumenon incorrectly. He explained in his "Critique of the Kantian philosophy", which first appeared as an appendix to The World as Will and Representation:

The difference between abstract and intuitive cognition, which Kant entirely overlooks, was the very one that ancient philosophers indicated as φαινόμενα [phainomena] and νοούμενα [nooumena]; the opposition and incommensurability between these terms proved very productive in the philosophemes of the Eleatics, in Plato's doctrine of Ideas, in the dialectic of the Megarics, and later in the scholastics, in the conflict between nominalism and realism. This latter conflict was the late development of a seed already present in the opposed tendencies of Plato and Aristotle. But Kant, who completely and irresponsibly neglected the issue for which the terms φαινομένα and νοούμενα were already in use, then took possession of the terms as if they were stray and ownerless, and used them as designations of things in themselves and their appearances.[36]

The noumenon's original meaning of "that which is thought" is not compatible with the "thing-in-itself," the latter being Kant's term for things as they exist apart from their existence as images in the mind of an observer.[citation needed] In a footnote to this passage, Schopenhauer provides the following passage from the Outlines of Pyrrhonism (Bk. I, ch. 13) of Sextus Empiricus to demonstrate the original distinction between phenomenon and noumenon according to ancient philosophers: νοούμενα φαινομένοις ἀντετίθη Ἀναξαγόρας ('Anaxagoras opposed what is thought to what appears.')

See also

Notes

  1. ^ Ontology

References

  1. ^ "Formal Epistemology". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. 2021.
  2. ^ "Noumenon | Definition of Noumenon by Webster's Online Dictionary". Archived from the original on 28 September 2011. Retrieved 10 September 2015. 1. intellectual conception of a thing as it is in itself, not as it is known through perception; 2. The of-itself-unknown and unknowable rational object, or thing-in-itself, which is distinguished from the phenomenon through which it is apprehended by the physical senses, and by which it is interpreted and understood; – so used in the philosophy of Kant and his followers.
  3. ^ "noumenon | philosophy". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 4 September 2017.
  4. ^ νοεῖν, νοῦς, νόος. Liddell, Henry George; Scott, Robert; A Greek–English Lexicon at the Perseus Project.
  5. ^ Harper, Douglas. "noumenon". Online Etymology Dictionary.
  6. ^ Bickmann, Claudia (2010). "9. Kant's Critical Concept of a Person: The Noumenal Sphere Grounding the Principle of Spirituality". Cultivating Personhood: Kant and Asian Philosophy. pp. 194–204. doi:10.1515/9783110226249.2.194. ISBN 978-3-11-022623-2.
  7. ^ Honderich, Ted, ed. (31 August 1995). The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press. p. 657. ISBN 0198661320. Retrieved 28 October 2014.
  8. ^ Hanna, Robert (2009). Completing the Picture of Kant's Metaphysics of Judgment. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  9. ^ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy on Kant's metaphysics.
  10. ^ The Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Macmillan, 1967, 1996) Volume 4, "Kant, Immanuel", section on "Critique of Pure Reason: Theme and Preliminaries", p. 308 ff.
  11. ^ The Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Macmillan, 1967, 1996) Volume 4, "Kant, Immanuel", section on "Transcendental Aesthetic", p. 310 ff.
  12. ^ The Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Macmillan, 1967, 1996) Volume 4, "Kant, Immanuel", section on "Pure Concepts of the Understanding", p. 311 ff.
  13. ^ See, e.g., The Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Macmillan, 1967, 1996) Volume 4, "Kant, Immanuel", section on "Critique of Pure Reason: Theme and Preliminaries", p. 308 ff.
  14. ^ See also, e.g., The Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Macmillan, 1967, 1996) Volume 4, "Kant, Immanuel", section on "Pure Concepts of the Understanding", p. 311 ff.
  15. ^ Kant 1999, p. 27, A256/B312.
  16. ^ Immanuel Kant (1781) Critique of Pure Reason, for example in A254/B310, p. 362 (Guyer and Wood), "The concept of a noumenon, i.e., of a thing that is not to be thought of as an object of the senses but rather as a thing-in-itself [...]"; But note that the terms are not used interchangeably throughout. The first reference to thing-in-itself comes many pages (A30) before the first reference to noumenon (A250). For a secondary or tertiary source, see: "Noumenon" in the Encyclopædia Britannica
  17. ^ "Noumenon: the name given to a thing when it is viewed as a transcendent object. The term 'negative noumenon' refers only to the recognition of something which is not an object of sensible intuition, while 'positive noumenon' refers to the (quite mistaken) attempt to know such a thing as an empirical object. These two terms are sometimes used loosely as synonyms for 'transcendental object' and 'thing-in-itself', respectively. (Cf. phenomenon.)" – Glossary of Kant's Technical Terms
  18. ^ Thing-in-itself: an object considered transcendentally apart from all the conditions under which a subject can gain knowledge of it via the physical senses. Hence the thing-in-itself is, by definition, unknowable via the physical senses. Sometimes used loosely as a synonym of noumenon. (Cf. appearance.)" – Glossary of Kant's Technical Terms. Palmquist defends his definitions of these terms in his article, "Six Perspectives on the Object in Kant's Theory of Knowledge", Dialectica 40:2 (1986), pp.121–151; revised and reprinted as Chapter VI in Palmquist's book, Kant's System of Perspectives (Lanham: University Press of America, 1993).
  19. ^ Oizerman, T. I., "Kant's Doctrine of the "Things in Themselves" and Noumena", Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Vol. 41, No. 3, Mar., 1981, 333–350; Karin de Boer, "Kant's Multi-Layered Conception of Things in Themselves, Transcendental Objects, and Monads", Kant-Studien 105/2, 2014, 221-260.
  20. ^ "Other interpreters have introduced an almost unending stream of varying suggestions as to how these terms ought to be used. A handful of examples will be sufficient to make this point clear, without any claim to represent an exhaustive overview. Perhaps the most commonly accepted view is expressed by Paulsen, who equates 'thing-in-itself' and 'noumenon', equates 'appearance' and 'phenomenon', distinguishes 'positive noumenon' and 'negative noumenon', and treats 'negative noumenon' as equivalent to 'transcendental object' [pp. 4:148-50, 154-5, 192]. Al-Azm and Wolff also seem satisfied to equate 'phenomenon' and 'appearance', though they both carefully distinguish 'thing-in-itself' from 'negative noumenon' and 'positive noumenon' [A4:520; W21:165, 313–5; s.a. W9:162]. Gotterbarn similarly equates the former pair, as well as 'thing-in-itself' and 'positive noumenon', but distinguishes between 'transcendental object', 'negative noumenon' and 'thing-in-itself' [G11: 201]. By contrast, Bird and George both distinguish between 'appearance' and 'phenomenon', but not between 'thing-in-itself' and 'noumenon' [B20:18,19, 53–7; G7:513-4n]; and Bird sometimes blurs the distinction between 'thing-in-itself' and 'transcendental object' as well.[2] Gram equates 'thing-in-itself' not with 'noumenon', but with 'phenomenon' [G13:1,5-6]! Allison cites different official meanings for each term, yet he tends to equate 'thing-in-itself' at times with 'negative noumenon' and at times with 'transcendental-object', usually ignoring the role of the 'positive noumenon' [A7:94; A10:58,69]. And Buchdahl responds to the fact that the thing-in-itself seems to be connected with each of the other object-terms by regarding it as 'Kant's umbrella term'.[3]" Stephen Palmquist on Kant's object terms
  21. ^ Kant 1999, Bxxvi-xxvii.
  22. ^ Kant 1999, p. 273, A256, B312.
  23. ^ "The Radical Unknowability of Kant's 'Thing in Itself'", Cogito 3:2 (March 1985), pp.101–115; revised and reprinted as Appendix V in Stephen Palmquist, Kant's System of Perspectives (Lanham: University Press of America, 1993).
  24. ^ Mattey, G. J.
  25. ^ Lecture notes by G. J. Mattey Archived 2010-06-12 at the Wayback Machine
  26. ^ a b c Kant 1999, p. 267 (NKS), A250/B307.
  27. ^ Kant 1999, p. 270 (NKS), B309.
  28. ^ Allison, H (2006). "Transcendental Realism, Empirical Realism, and Transcendental Idealism". Kantian Review. 11: 1–28. doi:10.1017/S1369415400002223. S2CID 171078596.
  29. ^ Kant 1999, A253/B310.
  30. ^ Kant 1999, p. 273, A256/B312.
  31. ^ Kant 1999, p. 156, B/137.
  32. ^ Kant 1999, p. 24, B/xx..
  33. ^ Rohmann, Chris. "Kant" A World of Ideas: A Dictionary of Important Theories, Concepts, Beliefs, and Thnkers. Ballantine Books, 1999.
  34. ^ Mattey, GJ. "Lecture Notes on the Critique of Pure Reason".
  35. ^ Anon., "Caird's Philosophy of Kant", Saturday Review of Politics, Literature, Science and Art, vol 44, Nov 3, 1877, pp. 559-60.
  36. ^ Schopenhauer, Arthur (2014). The World as Will and Representation, Volume 1. Translated by Norman, Judith; Welchman, Alistair; Janaway, Christopher. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. p. 506. ISBN 9780521871846.

Bibliography

Read other articles:

Amerikanlar buraya yönlendirilmektedir. AmerikalılarAmericansBirleşik Devletler bayrağıToplam nüfusca. 308,7 milyon[1](2010, sayım) ca. 329,5 milyon[2](2020, tahminî)Önemli nüfusa sahip bölgeler Meksika738.100–1.000.000[3][4] Kanada688.000–1.000.000[5][6] Hindistan2.694–700.000[7] Filipinler220.000–600.000[8][9] Almanya324.000[10] Brezilya260.000[...

يفتقر محتوى هذه المقالة إلى الاستشهاد بمصادر. فضلاً، ساهم في تطوير هذه المقالة من خلال إضافة مصادر موثوق بها. أي معلومات غير موثقة يمكن التشكيك بها وإزالتها. (ديسمبر 2018)   لمعانٍ أخرى، طالع كسر الخواطر (توضيح). كسر الخواطر مسلسل كسر الخواطر النوع دراما تأليف وداد الكواري

News-oriented digital broadcast television network This article is about the American television network. For the Canadian television channel formerly called CTV Newsnet, see CTV News Channel (Canadian TV channel). Television channel NewsNetTypeTerrestrial television networkCountryUnited StatesBroadcast areaNationwideHeadquartersCadillac, MichiganProgrammingLanguage(s)EnglishPicture format720p (HDTV, widescreen)OwnershipOwnerBridge Media NetworksParentBridge News, LLCKey peopleManoj Bhargava ...

علم بنسيلفانيا الاعتماد 29 أبريل 1900  الاختصاص بنسيلفانيا  تعديل مصدري - تعديل   علم بنسيلفانيا علم حاكم بنسيلفانيا علم بنسيلفانيا علم يمثل كومونولث بنسيلفانيا، يتكوّن من خلفية زرقاء عليها شعار النبالة للولاية.[1] اعتمد العلم في العام 1907. في صيف 2007 اقترح مشروع قان�...

Temporada de Estaduais 2023 Dados Período 7 de janeiro – dezembro ◄◄ Estaduais de 2022 Estaduais de 2024 ►► A lista a seguir traz dados acerca dos campeonatos estaduais de futebol realizados no Brasil em 2023.[1] Significados das colunas: Estado: nome do estado, listados em ordem alfabética. Copa do Brasil 2024: times classificados para a Copa do Brasil em sua edição de 2024 pelo Campeonato Estadual. [Ordem alfabética] Série D 2024: times classificados para o Campeonato Brasil...

هذه المقالة يتيمة إذ تصل إليها مقالات أخرى قليلة جدًا. فضلًا، ساعد بإضافة وصلة إليها في مقالات متعلقة بها. (أبريل 2019) مانويل راموس أوتيرو معلومات شخصية الميلاد 20 يوليو 1948  الوفاة 7 أكتوبر 1990 (42 سنة)   سان خوان، بورتوريكو  مواطنة الولايات المتحدة  الحياة العملية المد�...

Cúmulo globular M3 Datos de observación(Época J2000.0)Tipo Cúmulo globularAscensión recta 13h 42m 10sDeclinación +28° 23′Distancia 33.900 alMagnitud aparente (V) +6,2Tamaño aparente (V) 18,0 minutos de arcoConstelación Canes VenaticiCaracterísticas físicasRadio - alNúmero de estrellas 500.000 aprox.Magnitud absoluta (V) -Otras características -Otras designacionesM3, NGC 5272[editar datos en Wikidata] El Cúmulo globular M3 (también conocido como Objeto Messier 3, Mes...

Cette basilique n’est pas la seule basilique de la Sainte-Trinité. Cet article est une ébauche concernant une église ou une cathédrale et la Pologne. Vous pouvez partager vos connaissances en l’améliorant (comment ?) selon les recommandations des projets correspondants. Basilique de la Sainte-Trinité de Chełmża La basilique de Chełmża. Présentation Nom local Bazylika konkatedralna Świętej Trójcy Culte Catholique romain Type Cathédrale Rattachement Diocèse de ToruńArc...

Stasiun Yushima油島駅Stasiun Yushima pada November 2005LokasiHanaizumi-cho Yushima-aze, Ichinoseki-shi, Iwate-ken 029-3207JepangKoordinat38°47′49″N 141°10′32″E / 38.7969°N 141.1755°E / 38.7969; 141.1755Koordinat: 38°47′49″N 141°10′32″E / 38.7969°N 141.1755°E / 38.7969; 141.1755Pengelola JR EastJalur■ Jalur Utama TōhokuLetak dari pangkal427.0 km dari TokyoJumlah peron2 peron sampingJumlah jalur2KonstruksiJenis strukt...

エンゲルベルト・フンパーディンクEngelbert Humperdinck 2009年6月14日のラスベガスでのコンサートにて基本情報出生名 Arnold George Dorsey生誕 (1936-05-02) 1936年5月2日(87歳) イギリス領インド帝国、マドラス(現:チェンナイ)ジャンル イージー・リスニング担当楽器 ボーカル、ピアノ活動期間 1956年–現在 エンゲルベルト・フンパーディンク(Engelbert Humperdinck, 1936年5月2日 - )...

Artikel ini perlu diwikifikasi agar memenuhi standar kualitas Wikipedia. Anda dapat memberikan bantuan berupa penambahan pranala dalam, atau dengan merapikan tata letak dari artikel ini. Untuk keterangan lebih lanjut, klik [tampil] di bagian kanan. Mengganti markah HTML dengan markah wiki bila dimungkinkan. Tambahkan pranala wiki. Bila dirasa perlu, buatlah pautan ke artikel wiki lainnya dengan cara menambahkan [[ dan ]] pada kata yang bersangkutan (lihat WP:LINK untuk keterangan lebih lanjut...

Wappen von Heidelberg Weststadt Stadtteil von Heidelberg Lage des Stadtteils Weststadt in Heidelberg Koordinaten 49° 24′ 7″ N, 8° 41′ 5″ O49.4019444444448.6847222222222Koordinaten: 49° 24′ 7″ N, 8° 41′ 5″ O Fläche 1,74 km² Einwohner 12.654 (31. Dez. 2021) Bevölkerungsdichte 7272 Einwohner/km² Stadtteilnummer 004 Gliederung Stadtbezirke Weststadt-Ost (004 1) Weststadt-West (004 2) Alte Stadt...

هذه المقالة يتيمة إذ تصل إليها مقالات أخرى قليلة جدًا. فضلًا، ساعد بإضافة وصلة إليها في مقالات متعلقة بها. (فبراير 2019) اضغط هنا للاطلاع على كيفية قراءة التصنيف ملتهمة الحمض الهوائية نازعة النترات المرتبة التصنيفية نوع  التصنيف العلمي  فوق النطاق  حيويات مملكة عليا...

1951 Goodwood Trophy Non-championship race in the 1951 Formula One season Race detailsDate 29 September 1951Official name IV Goodwood TrophyLocation Chichester, West Sussex, UKCourse Goodwood CircuitCourse length 3.830 km (2.388 miles)Distance 15 laps, 57.450 km (35.817 miles)Pole positionDriver Tony Rolt Delage-ERA Grid positions set by ballotFastest lapDriver Giuseppe Farina Alfa RomeoTime 1:28.0PodiumFirst Giuseppe Farina Alfa RomeoSecond Reg Parnell FerrariThird Tony Rolt Delage-ERAMotor ...

Historical Middle Eastern alphabet Palmyrene alphabetPalmyrene inscribed tablet in the Musée du LouvreScript type Abjad Time period100 BCE to 300 CEDirectionright-to-left script LanguagesPalmyrene AramaicRelated scriptsParent systemsProto-Sinaitic alphabetPhoenician alphabetAramaic alphabetPalmyrene alphabetSister systemsAmmoniteBrāhmī [a]Edessan[1]Elymaic[1]Hatran[1]HebrewMandaic[1]Nabataean[1]PahlaviParthianISO 15924ISO 15924Palm (126), &...

Royal Horse GuardsHistóriaFundação 1650Quadro profissionalTipo british Army Cavalry regimentunidade militareditar - editar código-fonte - editar Wikidata O Royal Regiment of Horse Guards (The Blues) (RHG) foi um regimento de cavalaria do Exército Britânico, parte da Household Cavalry. Carga da brigada de cavalaria pesada, outubro de 1854 Criado em agosto de 1650 em Newcastle upon Tyne e County Durham por Sir Arthur Haselrigge sob as ordens de Oliver Cromwell como um Regimento de Cavalos...

Mathematical software Symbolic algebra redirects here. For the algebra of logic, see Symbolical algebra. A computer algebra system (CAS) or symbolic algebra system (SAS) is any mathematical software with the ability to manipulate mathematical expressions in a way similar to the traditional manual computations of mathematicians and scientists. The development of the computer algebra systems in the second half of the 20th century is part of the discipline of computer algebra or symbolic computa...

1997 American TV series or program IntensityPromotional artwork by Peter Ambush, for the Newark Star-Ledger's Scanner magazineBased onIntensity by Dean KoontzWritten byStephen TolkinDirected byYves SimoneauStarring John C. McGinley Molly Parker Deanna Milligan Piper Laurie Music byGeorge S. ClintonCountry of originUnited StatesOriginal languageEnglishProductionProducers Preston Fischer Dean R. Koontz Tom Patricia Deborah Edell Underwood CinematographyDavid FrancoEditorMichael Or...

Allied Forces Baltic ApproachesShield for Allied Forces Baltic ApproachesActive1962-2002Disbanded2002Countries Denmark West GermanyAllegiance North Atlantic Treaty OrganizationPart ofNATO Military Command StructureHeadquartersKarup, DenmarkCommandersNotablecommandersOtto K. LindKjeld HillingsøMilitary unit Allied Forces Baltic Approaches (BALTAP) was a Principal Subordinate Command (PSC) of the NATO Military Command Structure, with responsibility for the Baltic Sea area. It wa...

تحوي هذه المقالة أو هذا القسم ترجمة آلية. فضلًا، ساهم في تدقيقها وتحسينها أو إزالتها لأنها تخالف سياسات ويكيبيديا. (نقاش) (أبريل 2019) النزاع الحدودي بين إريتريا وجيبوتي   التاريخ وسيط property غير متوفر. بداية 10 يونيو 2008  نهاية 13 يونيو 2008  البلد جيبوتي  الموقع رأس دميرة...