In 1900, the mathematicianDavid Hilbert published a list of 23 unsolved mathematical problems. The list of problems turned out to be very influential.
After Hilbert's death, another problem was found in his writings; this is sometimes known as Hilbert's 24th problem today. This problem is about finding criteria to show that a solution to a problem is the simplest possible.[1]
Of the 23 problems, three were unresolved in 2012, three were too vague to be resolved, and six could be partially solved. Given the influence of the problems, the Clay Mathematics Institute formulated a similar list, called the Millennium Prize Problems in 2000.
Overview
The formulation of certain problems is better than that of others.
Of the cleanly-formulated Hilbert problems, problems 3, 7, 10, 11, 13, 14, 17, 19, 20, and 21 have a resolution that is accepted by consensus. On the other hand, problems 1, 2, 5, 9, 15, 18+, and 22 have solutions that have partial acceptance, but there exists some controversy as to whether it resolves the problem.[source?]
The solution for problem 18, the Kepler conjecture, uses a computer-assisted proof. This is controversial, because a human reader is unable to verify the proof in reasonable time.[source?]
That leaves 16, 8 – the Riemann hypothesis – and 12 unresolved. On this classification 4, 16, and 23 are too vague to ever be described as solved. The withdrawn 24 would also be in this class. 6 is considered as a problem in physics rather than in mathematics.[source?]
Proven to be impossible to prove or disprove within the Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with or without the Axiom of Choice (provided the Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with or without the Axiom of Choice is consistent, i.e., contains no two theorems such that one is a negation of the other). There is no consensus on whether this is a solution to the problem.
There is no consensus on whether results of Gödel and Gentzen give a solution to the problem as stated by Hilbert. Gödel's second incompleteness theorem, proved in 1931, shows that no proof of its consistency can be carried out within arithmetic itself. Gentzen's consistency proof (1936) shows that the consistency of arithmetic follows from the well-foundedness of the ordinal ε0.
Given any two polyhedra of equal volume, is it always possible to cut the first into finitely many polyhedral pieces which can be reassembled to yield the second?
Resolved by Emil Artin and Charles Delzell. Result: An upper limit was established for the number of square terms necessary. Finding a lower limit is still an open problem.
(a) Resolved. Result: yes (by Karl Reinhardt). (b) Resolved by Thomas Callister Hales using computer-aided proof. Result: cubic close packing and hexagonal close packing, both of which have a density of approximately 74%.[n 6]
↑According to Gray, most of the problems have been solved. Some were not defined completely, but enough progress has been made to consider them "solved"; Gray lists the fourth problem as too vague to say whether it has been solved.
↑The search for an axiomatic description of fundamental physics can be seen as an older wording for the search for the theory of everything.
↑D. Hilbert, "¨Uber die Gleichung neunten Grades", Math. Ann. 97 (1927), 243–250
↑It is not difficult to show that the problem has a partial solution within the space of single-valued analytic functions (Raudenbush). Some authors argue that Hilbert intended for a solution within the space of (multi-valued) algebraic functions, thus continuing his own work on algebraic functions and being a question about a possible extension of the Galois theory (see, for example, Abhyankar, Shreeram S. Abhyankar: Hilbert's Thirteenth Problem, Vitushkin, A. G. Vitushkin: On Hilbert's thirteenth problem and related questions, Chebotarev (N. G. Chebotarev, "On certain questions of the problem of resolvents") and others). It appears from one of Hilbert's papers [n 4] that this was his original intention for the problem.
The language of Hilbert there is "...Existenz von algebraischen Funktionen...",
i.e., "...existence of algebraic functions...".
As such, the problem is still unresolved.
↑Gray also lists the 18th problem as "open" in his 2000 book, because the sphere-packing problem (also known as the Kepler conjecture) was unsolved, but a solution to it has now been claimed (see reference below).
↑
Koji Nagata
"There is no axiomatic system for the quantum theory"
International Journal of Theoretical Physics,
Volume 48, Issue 12 (2009), Page 3532--3536,
DOI 10.1007/s10773-009-0158-z.
↑
Koji Nagata and Tadao Nakamura
"Can von Neumann's theory meet the Deutsch-Jozsa algorithm?"
International Journal of Theoretical Physics,
Volume 49, Issue 1 (2010), Page 162--170,
DOI 10.1007/s10773-009-0189-5.
↑
Koji Nagata, Chang-Liang Ren, and Tadao Nakamura
"Whether quantum computation can be almighty"
Advanced Studies in Theoretical Physics,
Volume 5, Number 1, (2011), Page 1--14.