In cryptography, a zero-knowledge proof is a protocol in which one party (the prover) can convince another party (the verifier) that some given statement is true, without conveying to the verifier any information beyond the mere fact of that statement's truth.[1] The intuition underlying zero-knowledge proofs is that it is trivial to prove possession of the relevant information simply by revealing it; the hard part is to prove this possession without revealing this information (or any aspect of it whatsoever).[2]
In light of the fact that one should be able to generate a proof of some statement only when in possession of certain secret information connected to the statement, the verifier, even after having become convinced of the statement's truth, should nonetheless remain unable to prove the statement to further third parties.
Zero-knowledge proofs can be interactive, meaning that the prover and verifier exchange messages according to some protocol, or noninteractive, meaning that the verifier is convinced by a single prover message and no other communication is needed. In the standard model, interaction is required, except for trivial proofs of BPP problems.[3] In the common random string and random oracle models, non-interactive zero-knowledge proofs exist. The Fiat–Shamir heuristic can be used to transform certain interactive zero-knowledge proofs into noninteractive ones.[4][5][6]
Abstract examples
The Ali Baba cave
Peggy randomly takes either path A or B, while Victor waits outside.
Victor chooses an exit path.
Peggy reliably appears at the exit Victor names.
There is a well-known story presenting the fundamental ideas of zero-knowledge proofs, first published in 1990 by Jean-Jacques Quisquater and others in their paper "How to Explain Zero-Knowledge Protocols to Your Children".[7] The two parties in the zero-knowledge proof story are Peggy as the prover of the statement, and Victor, the verifier of the statement.
In this story, Peggy has uncovered the secret word used to open a magic door in a cave. The cave is shaped like a ring, with the entrance on one side and the magic door blocking the opposite side. Victor wants to know whether Peggy knows the secret word; but Peggy, being a very private person, does not want to reveal her knowledge (the secret word) to Victor or to reveal the fact of her knowledge to the world in general.
They label the left and right paths from the entrance A and B. First, Victor waits outside the cave as Peggy goes in. Peggy takes either path A or B; Victor is not allowed to see which path she takes. Then, Victor enters the cave and shouts the name of the path he wants her to use to return, either A or B, chosen at random. Providing she really does know the magic word, this is easy: she opens the door, if necessary, and returns along the desired path.
However, suppose she did not know the word. Then, she would only be able to return by the named path if Victor were to give the name of the same path by which she had entered. Since Victor would choose A or B at random, she would have a 50% chance of guessing correctly. If they were to repeat this trick many times, say 20 times in a row, her chance of successfully anticipating all of Victor's requests would be reduced to 1 in 220, or 9.54 × 10−7.
Thus, if Peggy repeatedly appears at the exit Victor names, then he can conclude that it is extremely probable that Peggy does, in fact, know the secret word.
One side note with respect to third-party observers: even if Victor is wearing a hidden camera that records the whole transaction, the only thing the camera will record is in one case Victor shouting "A!" and Peggy appearing at A or in the other case Victor shouting "B!" and Peggy appearing at B. A recording of this type would be trivial for any two people to fake (requiring only that Peggy and Victor agree beforehand on the sequence of As and Bs that Victor will shout). Such a recording will certainly never be convincing to anyone but the original participants. In fact, even a person who was present as an observer at the original experiment should be unconvinced, since Victor and Peggy could have orchestrated the whole "experiment" from start to finish.
Further, if Victor chooses his As and Bs by flipping a coin on-camera, this protocol loses its zero-knowledge property; the on-camera coin flip would probably be convincing to any person watching the recording later. Thus, although this does not reveal the secret word to Victor, it does make it possible for Victor to convince the world in general that Peggy has that knowledge—counter to Peggy's stated wishes. However, digital cryptography generally "flips coins" by relying on a pseudo-random number generator, which is akin to a coin with a fixed pattern of heads and tails known only to the coin's owner. If Victor's coin behaved this way, then again it would be possible for Victor and Peggy to have faked the experiment, so using a pseudo-random number generator would not reveal Peggy's knowledge to the world in the same way that using a flipped coin would.
Peggy could prove to Victor that she knows the magic word, without revealing it to him, in a single trial. If both Victor and Peggy go together to the mouth of the cave, Victor can watch Peggy go in through A and come out through B. This would prove with certainty that Peggy knows the magic word, without revealing the magic word to Victor. However, such a proof could be observed by a third party, or recorded by Victor and such a proof would be convincing to anybody. In other words, Peggy could not refute such proof by claiming she colluded with Victor, and she is therefore no longer in control of who is aware of her knowledge.
Two balls and the colour-blind friend
Imagine your friend "Victor" is red-green colour-blind (while you are not) and you have two balls: one red and one green, but otherwise identical. To Victor, the balls seem completely identical. Victor is skeptical that the balls are actually distinguishable. You want to prove to Victor that the balls are in fact differently coloured, but nothing else. In particular, you do not want to reveal which ball is the red one and which is the green.
Here is the proof system. You give the two balls to Victor and he puts them behind his back. Next, he takes one of the balls and brings it out from behind his back and displays it. He then places it behind his back again and then chooses to reveal just one of the two balls, picking one of the two at random with equal probability. He will ask you, "Did I switch the ball?" This whole procedure is then repeated as often as necessary.
By looking at the balls' colours, you can, of course, say with certainty whether or not he switched them. On the other hand, if the balls were the same colour and hence indistinguishable, there is no way you could guess correctly with probability higher than 50%.
Since the probability that you would have randomly succeeded at identifying each switch/non-switch is 50%, the probability of having randomly succeeded at all switch/non-switches approaches zero ("soundness"). If you and your friend repeat this "proof" multiple times (e.g. 20 times), your friend should become convinced ("completeness") that the balls are indeed differently coloured.
The above proof is zero-knowledge because your friend never learns which ball is green and which is red; indeed, he gains no knowledge about how to distinguish the balls.[8]
Where's Waldo
One well-known example of a zero-knowledge proof is the "Where's Waldo" example. In this example, the prover wants to prove to the verifier that they know where Waldo is on a page in a Where's Waldo? book, without revealing his location to the verifier.[9]
The prover starts by taking a large black board with a small hole in it, the size of Waldo. The board is twice the size of the book in both directions, so the verifier cannot see where on the page the prover is placing it. The prover then places the board over the page so that Waldo is in the hole.[9]
The verifier can now look through the hole and see Waldo, but cannot see any other part of the page. Therefore, the prover has proven to the verifier that they know where Waldo is, without revealing any other information about his location.[9]
This example is not a perfect zero-knowledge proof, because the prover does reveal some information about Waldo's location, such as his body position. However, it is a decent illustration of the basic concept of a zero-knowledge proof.
A zero-knowledge proof of some statement must satisfy three properties:
Completeness: if the statement is true, then an honest verifier (that is, one following the protocol properly) will be convinced of this fact by an honest prover.
Soundness: if the statement is false, then no cheating prover can convince an honest verifier that it is true, except with some small probability.
Zero-knowledge: if the statement is true, then no verifier learns anything other than the fact that the statement is true. In other words, just knowing the statement (not the secret) is sufficient to imagine a scenario showing that the prover knows the secret. This is formalized by showing that every verifier has some simulator that, given only the statement to be proved (and no access to the prover), can produce a transcript that "looks like" an interaction between an honest prover and the verifier in question.
The first two of these are properties of more general interactive proof systems. The third is what makes the proof zero-knowledge.[10]
Zero-knowledge proofs are not proofs in the mathematical sense of the term because there is some small probability, the soundness error, that a cheating prover will be able to convince the verifier of a false statement. In other words, zero-knowledge proofs are probabilistic "proofs" rather than deterministic proofs. However, there are techniques to decrease the soundness error to negligibly small values (for example, guessing correctly on a hundred or thousand binary decisions has a 1/2100 or 1/21000 soundness error, respectively. As the number of bits increases, the soundness error decreases toward zero).
A formal definition of zero-knowledge must use some computational model, the most common one being that of a Turing machine. Let P, V, and S be Turing machines. An interactive proof system with (P,V) for a language L is zero-knowledge if for any probabilistic polynomial time (PPT) verifier there exists a PPT simulator S such that:
where View[P(x)↔(x,z)] is a record of the interactions between P(x) and V(x,z). The prover P is modeled as having unlimited computation power (in practice, P usually is a probabilistic Turing machine). Intuitively, the definition states that an interactive proof system (P,V) is zero-knowledge if for any verifier there exists an efficient simulator S (depending on that can reproduce the conversation between P and on any given input. The auxiliary string z in the definition plays the role of "prior knowledge" (including the random coins of ). The definition implies that cannot use any prior knowledge string z to mine information out of its conversation with P, because if S is also given this prior knowledge then it can reproduce the conversation between and P just as before. [citation needed]
The definition given is that of perfect zero-knowledge. Computational zero-knowledge is obtained by requiring that the views of the verifier and the simulator are only computationally indistinguishable, given the auxiliary string. [citation needed]
Practical examples
Discrete log of a given value
These ideas can be applied to a more realistic cryptography application. Peggy wants to prove to Victor that she knows the discrete logarithm of a given value in a given group.[11]
For example, given a value y, a large primep, and a generator , she wants to prove that she knows a value x such that gx ≡ y (mod p), without revealing x. Indeed, knowledge of x could be used as a proof of identity, in that Peggy could have such knowledge because she chose a random value x that she did not reveal to anyone, computed y = gx mod p, and distributed the value of y to all potential verifiers, such that at a later time, proving knowledge of x is equivalent to proving identity as Peggy.
The protocol proceeds as follows: in each round, Peggy generates a random number r, computes C = gr mod p and discloses this to Victor. After receiving C, Victor randomly issues one of the following two requests: he either requests that Peggy discloses the value of r, or the value of (x + r) mod (p − 1).
Victor can verify either answer; if he requested r, he can then compute gr mod p and verify that it matches C. If he requested (x + r) mod (p − 1), then he can verify that C is consistent with this, by computing g(x + r) mod (p − 1) mod p and verifying that it matches (C · y) mod p. If Peggy indeed knows the value of x, then she can respond to either one of Victor's possible challenges.
If Peggy knew or could guess which challenge Victor is going to issue, then she could easily cheat and convince Victor that she knows x when she does not: if she knows that Victor is going to request r, then she proceeds normally: she picks r, computes C = gr mod p, and discloses C to Victor; she will be able to respond to Victor's challenge. On the other hand, if she knows that Victor will request (x + r) mod (p − 1), then she picks a random value r′, computes C′ ≡ gr′ · (gx)−1 mod p, and discloses C′ to Victor as the value of C that he is expecting. When Victor challenges her to reveal (x + r) mod (p − 1), she reveals r′, for which Victor will verify consistency, since he will in turn compute gr′ mod p, which matches C′ · y, since Peggy multiplied by the modular multiplicative inverse of y.
However, if in either one of the above scenarios Victor issues a challenge other than the one she was expecting and for which she manufactured the result, then she will be unable to respond to the challenge under the assumption of infeasibility of solving the discrete log for this group. If she picked r and disclosed C = gr mod p, then she will be unable to produce a valid (x + r) mod (p − 1) that would pass Victor's verification, given that she does not know x. And if she picked a value r′ that poses as (x + r) mod (p − 1), then she would have to respond with the discrete log of the value that she disclosed – but Peggy does not know this discrete log, since the value C she disclosed was obtained through arithmetic with known values, and not by computing a power with a known exponent.
Thus, a cheating prover has a 0.5 probability of successfully cheating in one round. By executing a large-enough number of rounds, the probability of a cheating prover succeeding can be made arbitrarily low.
To show that the above interactive proof gives zero knowledge other than the fact that Peggy knows x, one can use similar arguments as used in the above proof of completeness and soundness. Specifically, a simulator, say Simon, who does not know x, can simulate the exchange between Peggy and Victor by the following procedure. Firstly, Simon randomly flips a fair coin. If the result is "heads", then he picks a random value r, computes C = gr mod p, and discloses C as if it is a message from Peggy to Victor. Then Simon also outputs a message "request the value of r" as if it is sent from Victor to Peggy, and immediately outputs the value of r as if it is sent from Peggy to Victor. A single round is complete. On the other hand, if the coin flipping result is "tails", then Simon picks a random number r′, computes C′ = gr′ · y−1 mod p, and discloses C′ as if it is a message from Peggy to Victor. Then Simon outputs "request the value of (x + r) mod (p − 1)" as if it is a message from Victor to Peggy. Finally, Simon outputs the value of r′ as if it is the response from Peggy back to Victor. A single round is complete. By the previous arguments when proving the completeness and soundness, the interactive communication simulated by Simon is indistinguishable from the true correspondence between Peggy and Victor. The zero-knowledge property is thus guaranteed.
Short summary
Peggy proves to know the value of x (for example her password).
Peggy and Victor agree on a prime p and a generator of the multiplicative group of the field ℤp.
Peggy calculates the value y = gx mod p and transfers the value to Victor.
The following two steps are repeated a (large) number of times.
Peggy repeatedly picks a random value r ∈ U[0, p − 2] and calculates C = gr mod p. She transfers the value C to Victor.
Victor asks Peggy to calculate and transfer either the value (x + r) mod (p − 1) or the value r. In the first case Victor verifies C · y ≡ g(x + r) mod (p − 1) mod p. In the second case he verifies C = gr mod p.
The value (x + r) mod (p − 1) can be seen as the encrypted value of x mod (p − 1). If r is truly random, uniformly distributed between zero and p − 2, then this does not leak any information about x (see one-time pad).
In this scenario, Peggy knows a Hamiltonian cycle for a large graphG. Victor knows G but not the cycle (e.g., Peggy has generated G and revealed it to him.) Finding a Hamiltonian cycle given a large graph is believed to be computationally infeasible, since its corresponding decision version is known to be NP-complete. Peggy will prove that she knows the cycle without simply revealing it (perhaps Victor is interested in buying it but wants verification first, or maybe Peggy is the only one who knows this information and is proving her identity to Victor).
To show that Peggy knows this Hamiltonian cycle, she and Victor play several rounds of a game:
At the beginning of each round, Peggy creates H, a graph which is isomorphic to G (that is, H is just like G except that all the vertices have different names). Since it is trivial to translate a Hamiltonian cycle between isomorphic graphs with known isomorphism, if Peggy knows a Hamiltonian cycle for G then she also must know one for H.
Peggy commits to H. She could do so by using a cryptographic commitment scheme. Alternatively, she could number the vertices of H. Next, for each edge of H, on a small piece of paper, she writes down the two vertices that the edge joins. Then she puts all these pieces of paper face down on a table. The purpose of this commitment is that Peggy is not able to change H while, at the same time, Victor has no information about H.
Victor then randomly chooses one of two questions to ask Peggy. He can either ask her to show the isomorphism between H and G (see graph isomorphism problem), or he can ask her to show a Hamiltonian cycle in H.
If Peggy is asked to show that the two graphs are isomorphic, then she first uncovers all of H (e.g. by turning over all pieces of papers that she put on the table) and then provides the vertex translations that map G to H. Victor can verify that they are indeed isomorphic.
If Peggy is asked to prove that she knows a Hamiltonian cycle in H, then she translates her Hamiltonian cycle in G onto H and only uncovers the edges on the Hamiltonian cycle. That is, Peggy only turns over exactly |V(G)| of the pieces of paper that correspond to the edges of the Hamiltonian cycle, while leaving the rest still face-down. This is enough for Victor to check that H does indeed contain a Hamiltonian cycle.
It is important that the commitment to the graph be such that Victor can verify, in the second case, that the cycle is really made of edges from H. This can be done by, for example, committing to every edge (or lack thereof) separately.
Completeness
If Peggy does know a Hamiltonian cycle in G, then she can easily satisfy Victor's demand for either the graph isomorphism producing H from G (which she had committed to in the first step) or a Hamiltonian cycle in H (which she can construct by applying the isomorphism to the cycle in G).
Zero-knowledge
Peggy's answers do not reveal the original Hamiltonian cycle in G. In each round, Victor will learn only H's isomorphism to G or a Hamiltonian cycle in H. He would need both answers for a single H to discover the cycle in G, so the information remains unknown as long as Peggy can generate a distinct H every round. If Peggy does not know of a Hamiltonian cycle in G, but somehow knew in advance what Victor would ask to see each round, then she could cheat. For example, if Peggy knew ahead of time that Victor would ask to see the Hamiltonian cycle in H, then she could generate a Hamiltonian cycle for an unrelated graph. Similarly, if Peggy knew in advance that Victor would ask to see the isomorphism then she could simply generate an isomorphic graph H (in which she also does not know a Hamiltonian cycle). Victor could simulate the protocol by himself (without Peggy) because he knows what he will ask to see. Therefore, Victor gains no information about the Hamiltonian cycle in G from the information revealed in each round.
Soundness
If Peggy does not know the information, then she can guess which question Victor will ask and generate either a graph isomorphic to G or a Hamiltonian cycle for an unrelated graph, but since she does not know a Hamiltonian cycle for G, she cannot do both. With this guesswork, her chance of fooling Victor is 2−n, where n is the number of rounds. For all realistic purposes, it is infeasibly difficult to defeat a zero-knowledge proof with a reasonable number of rounds in this way.
Variants of zero-knowledge
Different variants of zero-knowledge can be defined by formalizing the intuitive concept of what is meant by the output of the simulator "looking like" the execution of the real proof protocol in the following ways:
We speak of perfect zero-knowledge if the distributions produced by the simulator and the proof protocol are distributed exactly the same. This is for instance the case in the first example above.
Statistical zero-knowledge[13] means that the distributions are not necessarily exactly the same, but they are statistically close, meaning that their statistical difference is a negligible function.
We speak of computational zero-knowledge if no efficient algorithm can distinguish the two distributions.
Zero knowledge types
There are various types of zero-knowledge proofs:
Proof of knowledge: the knowledge is hidden in the exponent like in the example shown above.
Research in zero-knowledge proofs has been motivated by authentication systems where one party wants to prove its identity to a second party via some secret information (such as a password) but does not want the second party to learn anything about this secret. This is called a "zero-knowledge proof of knowledge". However, a password is typically too small or insufficiently random to be used in many schemes for zero-knowledge proofs of knowledge. A zero-knowledge password proof is a special kind of zero-knowledge proof of knowledge that addresses the limited size of passwords.[citation needed]
In April 2015, the one-out-of-many proofs protocol (a Sigma protocol) was introduced.[14] In August 2021, Cloudflare, an American web infrastructure and security company, decided to use the one-out-of-many proofs mechanism for private web verification using vendor hardware.[15]
Ethical behavior
One of the uses of zero-knowledge proofs within cryptographic protocols is to enforce honest behavior while maintaining privacy. Roughly, the idea is to force a user to prove, using a zero-knowledge proof, that its behavior is correct according to the protocol.[16][17] Because of soundness, we know that the user must really act honestly in order to be able to provide a valid proof. Because of zero knowledge, we know that the user does not compromise the privacy of its secrets in the process of providing the proof.[citation needed]
Nuclear disarmament
In 2016, the Princeton Plasma Physics Laboratory and Princeton University demonstrated a technique that may have applicability to future nuclear disarmament talks. It would allow inspectors to confirm whether or not an object is indeed a nuclear weapon without recording, sharing, or revealing the internal workings, which might be secret.[18]
Blockchains
Zero-knowledge proofs were applied in the Zerocoin and Zerocash protocols, which culminated in the birth of Zcoin[19] (later rebranded as Firo in 2020)[20] and Zcash cryptocurrencies in 2016. Zerocoin has a built-in mixing model that does not trust any peers or centralised mixing providers to ensure anonymity.[19] Users can transact in a base currency and can cycle the currency into and out of Zerocoins.[21] The Zerocash protocol uses a similar model (a variant known as a non-interactive zero-knowledge proof)[22] except that it can obscure the transaction amount, while Zerocoin cannot. Given significant restrictions of transaction data on the Zerocash network, Zerocash is less prone to privacy timing attacks when compared to Zerocoin. However, this additional layer of privacy can cause potentially undetected hyperinflation of Zerocash supply because fraudulent coins cannot be tracked.[19][23]
In 2018, Bulletproofs were introduced. Bulletproofs are an improvement from non-interactive zero-knowledge proofs where a trusted setup is not needed.[24] It was later implemented into the Mimblewimble protocol (which the Grin and Beam cryptocurrencies are based upon) and Monero cryptocurrency.[25] In 2019, Firo implemented the Sigma protocol, which is an improvement on the Zerocoin protocol without trusted setup.[26][14] In the same year, Firo introduced the Lelantus protocol, an improvement on the Sigma protocol, where the former hides the origin and amount of a transaction.[27]
Decentralized Identifiers
Zero-knowledge proofs by their nature can enhance privacy in identity-sharing systems, which are vulnerable to data breaches and identity theft. When integrated to a decentralized identifier system, ZKPs add an extra layer of encryption on DID documents.[28]
History
Zero-knowledge proofs were first conceived in 1985 by Shafi Goldwasser, Silvio Micali, and Charles Rackoff in their paper "The Knowledge Complexity of Interactive Proof-Systems".[16] This paper introduced the IP hierarchy of interactive proof systems (see interactive proof system) and conceived the concept of knowledge complexity, a measurement of the amount of knowledge about the proof transferred from the prover to the verifier. They also gave the first zero-knowledge proof for a concrete problem, that of deciding quadratic nonresidues mod m. Together with a paper by László Babai and Shlomo Moran, this landmark paper invented interactive proof systems, for which all five authors won the first Gödel Prize in 1993.
In their own words, Goldwasser, Micali, and Rackoff say:
Of particular interest is the case where this additional knowledge is essentially 0 and we show that [it] is possible to interactively prove that a number is quadratic non residue mod m releasing 0 additional knowledge. This is surprising as no efficient algorithm for deciding quadratic residuosity mod m is known when m’s factorization is not given. Moreover, all known NP proofs for this problem exhibit the prime factorization of m. This indicates that adding interaction to the proving process, may decrease the amount of knowledge that must be communicated in order to prove a theorem.
The quadratic nonresidue problem has both an NP and a co-NP algorithm, and so lies in the intersection of NP and co-NP. This was also true of several other problems for which zero-knowledge proofs were subsequently discovered, such as an unpublished proof system by Oded Goldreich verifying that a two-prime modulus is not a Blum integer.[29]
Oded Goldreich, Silvio Micali, and Avi Wigderson took this one step further, showing that, assuming the existence of unbreakable encryption, one can create a zero-knowledge proof system for the NP-complete graph coloring problem with three colors. Since every problem in NP can be efficiently reduced to this problem, this means that, under this assumption, all problems in NP have zero-knowledge proofs.[30] The reason for the assumption is that, as in the above example, their protocols require encryption. A commonly cited sufficient condition for the existence of unbreakable encryption is the existence of one-way functions, but it is conceivable that some physical means might also achieve it.
On top of this, they also showed that the graph nonisomorphism problem, the complement of the graph isomorphism problem, has a zero-knowledge proof. This problem is in co-NP, but is not currently known to be in either NP or any practical class. More generally, Russell Impagliazzo and Moti Yung as well as Ben-Or et al. would go on to show that, also assuming one-way functions or unbreakable encryption, there are zero-knowledge proofs for all problems in IP = PSPACE, or in other words, anything that can be proved by an interactive proof system can be proved with zero knowledge.[31][32]
Not liking to make unnecessary assumptions, many theorists sought a way to eliminate the necessity of one way functions. One way this was done was with multi-prover interactive proof systems (see interactive proof system), which have multiple independent provers instead of only one, allowing the verifier to "cross-examine" the provers in isolation to avoid being misled. It can be shown that, without any intractability assumptions, all languages in NP have zero-knowledge proofs in such a system.[33]
It turns out that, in an Internet-like setting, where multiple protocols may be executed concurrently, building zero-knowledge proofs is more challenging. The line of research investigating concurrent zero-knowledge proofs was initiated by the work of Dwork, Naor, and Sahai.[34] One particular development along these lines has been the development of witness-indistinguishable proof protocols. The property of witness-indistinguishability is related to that of zero-knowledge, yet witness-indistinguishable protocols do not suffer from the same problems of concurrent execution.[35]
Another variant of zero-knowledge proofs are non-interactive zero-knowledge proofs. Blum, Feldman, and Micali showed that a common random string shared between the prover and the verifier is enough to achieve computational zero-knowledge without requiring interaction.[5][6]
Zero-Knowledge Proof protocols
The most popular interactive or non-interactive zero-knowledge proof (e.g., zk-SNARK) protocols can be broadly categorized in the following four categories: Succinct Non-Interactive ARguments of Knowledge (SNARK), Scalable Transparent ARgument of Knowledge (STARK), Verifiable Polynomial Delegation (VPD), and Succinct Non-interactive ARGuments (SNARG). A list of zero-knowledge proof protocols and libraries is provided below along with comparisons based on transparency, universality, plausible post-quantum security, and programming paradigm.[36] A transparent protocol is one that does not require any trusted setup and uses public randomness. A universal protocol is one that does not require a separate trusted setup for each circuit. Finally, a plausibly post-quantum protocol is one that is not susceptible to known attacks involving quantum algorithms.
^Chaum, David; Evertse, Jan-Hendrik; van de Graaf, Jeroen (1988). "An Improved Protocol for Demonstrating Possession of Discrete Logarithms and Some Generalizations". Advances in Cryptology — EUROCRYPT '87. Lecture Notes in Computer Science. Vol. 304. pp. 127–141. doi:10.1007/3-540-39118-5_13. ISBN978-3-540-19102-5.
^ abBünz, B; Bootle, D; Boneh, A (2018). "Bulletproofs: Short Proofs for Confidential Transactions and More". 2018 IEEE Symposium on Security and Privacy (SP). San Francisco, California. pp. 315–334. doi:10.1109/SP.2018.00020. ISBN978-1-5386-4353-2. S2CID3337741.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link)
^Odendaal, Hansie; Sharrock, Cayle; Heerden, SW. "Bulletproofs and Mimblewimble". Tari Labs University. Archived from the original on 29 September 2020. Retrieved 3 December 2020.
^Ben-Sasson, Eli; Chiesa, Alessandro; Genkin, Daniel; Tromer, Eran; Virza, Madars (2013). "SNARKs for C: Verifying Program Executions Succinctly and in Zero Knowledge". Advances in Cryptology – CRYPTO 2013. Lecture Notes in Computer Science. Vol. 8043. pp. 90–108. doi:10.1007/978-3-642-40084-1_6. hdl:1721.1/87953. ISBN978-3-642-40083-4.
^Wahby, Riad S.; Setty, Srinath; Ren, Zuocheng; Blumberg, Andrew J.; Walfish, Michael (2015). "Efficient RAM and Control Flow in Verifiable Outsourced Computation". Proceedings 2015 Network and Distributed System Security Symposium. doi:10.14722/ndss.2015.23097. ISBN978-1-891562-38-9.
^Eberhardt, Jacob; Tai, Stefan (July 2018). "ZoKrates - Scalable Privacy-Preserving Off-Chain Computations". 2018 IEEE International Conference on Internet of Things (IThings) and IEEE Green Computing and Communications (GreenCom) and IEEE Cyber, Physical and Social Computing (CPSCom) and IEEE Smart Data (SmartData). pp. 1084–1091. doi:10.1109/Cybermatics_2018.2018.00199. ISBN978-1-5386-7975-3. S2CID49473237.
^Kosba, Ahmed; Papamanthou, Charalampos; Shi, Elaine (May 2018). "XJsnark: A Framework for Efficient Verifiable Computation". 2018 IEEE Symposium on Security and Privacy (SP). pp. 944–961. doi:10.1109/SP.2018.00018. ISBN978-1-5386-4353-2.
^Zhang, Yupeng; Genkin, Daniel; Katz, Jonathan; Papadopoulos, Dimitrios; Papamanthou, Charalampos (May 2018). "VRAM: Faster Verifiable RAM with Program-Independent Preprocessing". 2018 IEEE Symposium on Security and Privacy (SP). pp. 908–925. doi:10.1109/SP.2018.00013. ISBN978-1-5386-4353-2.
^Zhang, Jiaheng; Xie, Tiancheng; Zhang, Yupeng; Song, Dawn (May 2020). "Transparent Polynomial Delegation and Its Applications to Zero Knowledge Proof". 2020 IEEE Symposium on Security and Privacy (SP). pp. 859–876. doi:10.1109/SP40000.2020.00052. ISBN978-1-7281-3497-0.
^Ames, Scott; Hazay, Carmit; Ishai, Yuval; Venkitasubramaniam, Muthuramakrishnan (30 October 2017). "Ligero". Proceedings of the 2017 ACM SIGSAC Conference on Computer and Communications Security. Association for Computing Machinery. pp. 2087–2104. doi:10.1145/3133956.3134104. ISBN9781450349468. S2CID5348527.
ChinsukoJenisbiskuitTempat asalJepangDaerahOkinawaBahan utamaterigu, gula, lemak babiSunting kotak info • L • BBantuan penggunaan templat ini Media: Chinsuko Chinsuko (ちんすこう、金楚糕、きんそう糕 atau 珍楚糕code: ja is deprecated , chinsukō) adalah kue kering tradisional khas Okinawa yang berasal dari resep zaman Kerajaan Ryukyu. Kue ini mirip biskuit, bahan utamanya terigu, gula, dan lemak babi. Di tempat-tempat wisata di Prefektur Okinawa, chins...
Listrik adalah sumber yang terjadi energi ke satelit dunia . Artikel ini merupakan bagain dari seriListrik dan MagnetMichael Faraday. Bapak kelistrikan dunia, dan sosok penting pada ilmu kemagnetan. Buku rujukan Statika listrik Muatan listrik Medan listrik Insulator Konduktor Ketribolistrikan Induksi Listrik Statis Hukum Coulomb Hukum Gauss Fluks listrik / energi potensial Momen polaritas listirk Statika magnet Hukum Ampere Medan magnet Magnetisasi Fluks magnetik Kaidah tangan kanan Kaid...
Village in North Kingstown, Rhode Island, US United States historic placeWickford Historic DistrictU.S. National Register of Historic PlacesU.S. Historic district Wickford from the air, looking east.Show map of Rhode IslandShow map of the United StatesLocationNorth Kingstown, Rhode IslandCoordinates41°34′26″N 71°27′41″W / 41.57389°N 71.46139°W / 41.57389; -71.46139Area380 acres (150 ha)ArchitectTefft, T.A.; Sawtelle, W.C.Architectural styleGreek ...
Artikel ini mungkin terdampak dengan peristiwa terkini: Invasi Rusia ke Ukraina 2022. Informasi di halaman ini bisa berubah setiap saat. Letak Oblast Chernihiw di Ukraina Oblast Chernihiv merupakan sebuah oblast di Ukraina yang memiliki luas wilayah 31.865 km² dan populasi 1.156.609 jiwa (2006). Ibu kotanya ialah Chernihiv. lbsPembagian administratif Ukraina Oblast Cherkasy · Chernihiv · Chernivtsi · Krimea · Dnipropetrovsk · Donets...
Cet article est une ébauche concernant une localité albanaise. Vous pouvez partager vos connaissances en l’améliorant (comment ?) selon les recommandations des projets correspondants. PustecGéographiePays AlbanieQarku KorçëChef-lieu Pustec (en)Coordonnées 40° 47′ 13″ N, 20° 54′ 08″ EDémographiePopulation 3 290 hab. (2011)FonctionnementStatut Bashkia (d)IdentifiantsCode postal 7020Immatriculation KO Géolocalisation sur la ...
Defunct flying squadron of the Royal Air Force No. 158 Squadron RAFActive9 May 1918 – 20 Nov 1918 14 Feb 1942 – 31 Dec 1945Country United KingdomBranch Royal Air ForceRoleBomber Squadron Transport SquadronPart ofNo. 4 Group RAF, Bomber Command (Feb 42 – Jun 45)[1] No. 4 Group RAF, Transport Command (Jun 45 – Dec 45)[2]Motto(s)Strength in unity[3][4]InsigniaSquadron Badge heraldryA circular chain of seven links[3][4]The chain is indi...
1976 Colombo summit conference 5th Summit of the Non-Aligned MovementVenue of the SummitHost country Sri LankaDate16–19 August 1976CitiesColomboChairSirimavo Bandaranaike (Prime Minister of Sri Lanka)Follows4th Summit of the Non-Aligned Movement (Algiers, Algeria)Precedes6th Summit of the Non-Aligned Movement (Havana, Cuba) 5th Summit of the Non-Aligned Movement on 16–19 August 1976 in Colombo, Sri Lanka was the conference of Heads of State or Government of the Non-Aligne...
Indian telecommunications company Not to be confused with Reliance Communications or Jio Platforms. Reliance Jio Infocomm LimitedJio's headquarters in RCP, Navi MumbaiTrade nameJioCompany typeSubsidiaryIndustryTelecommunicationsFounded15 February 2007; 17 years ago (2007-02-15)FounderMukesh AmbaniHeadquartersReliance Corporate Park, Ghansoli, Navi Mumbai, Maharashtra, IndiaArea servedIndiaKey peopleAkash Ambani(Chairman)[1]Sandip Das(Managing Director)ProductsFixed-l...
Запрос «Пугачёва» перенаправляется сюда; см. также другие значения. Алла Пугачёва На фестивале «Славянский базар в Витебске», 2016 год Основная информация Полное имя Алла Борисовна Пугачёва Дата рождения 15 апреля 1949(1949-04-15) (75 лет) Место рождения Москва, СССР[1]...
Prefecture-level city in Jilin, People's Republic of China Prefecture-level city in Jilin, People's Republic of ChinaSiping 四平市Prefecture-level citySiping martyr cenotaph, in SipingLocation of Siping City (yellow) in Jilin (light grey) and ChinaSipingLocation of the city centre in JilinCoordinates (Siping municipal government): 43°10′00″N 124°21′02″E / 43.1668°N 124.3506°E / 43.1668; 124.3506CountryPeople's Republic of ChinaProvinceJilinCounty-lev...
American politician (1850–1926) William E. EnglishMember of the U.S. House of Representativesfrom Indiana's 7th districtIn officeMay 22, 1884 – March 3, 1885Preceded byStanton J. PeelleSucceeded byWilliam D. Bynum Personal detailsBornWilliam Eastin English(1850-11-03)November 3, 1850Englishton Park, Lexington, Indiana, U.S.DiedApril 29, 1926(1926-04-29) (aged 75)Indianapolis, Indiana, U.S.Resting placeCrown Hill CemeteryPolitical partyRepublicanOther politicalaff...
For the 1957 opera, see Dialogues of the Carmelites. 1960 French filmDialogue of the CarmelitesDirected byRaymond Léopold Bruckberger(as R.L. Bruckberger)Philippe AgostiniWritten byRaymond Léopold Bruckberger(R.L. Bruckberger)(adaptation)Philippe Agostini(adaptation)Screenplay byRaymond Léopold Bruckberger(R.L. Bruckberger)Philippe AgostiniBased onGertrud von Le Fort (novek)Georges Bernanos (play)StarringJeanne MoreauAlida ValliMadeleine RenaudPascale AudretPierre BrasseurJean-Louis Barrau...
French high-speed mail trainset TGV La PosteTGV La Poste trainsetIn service1984- 27 June 2015[1]ManufacturerGEC-AlsthomFamily nameTGVNumber built2+1⁄2 (new) + 1 (converted)Number preserved3 + 1⁄2 spare setFormation10 cars (2 power cars, 8 postal cars)OperatorsSNCF for La PosteSpecificationsTrain length200 m (656 ft 2 in)Width2.904 m (9 ft 6.3 in)Maximum speed270 km/h (168 mph)Power output6,800 kW (9,119 hp) @ 25 kVElectric ...
Ciclo circadiano della temperatura corporea L'omeostasi (dal greco omeo - e - stasi, simile posizione[1]) è la tendenza naturale al raggiungimento di una relativa stabilità, sia delle proprietà chimico-fisiche interne sia comportamentali, che accomuna tutti gli organismi viventi, per i quali tale regime dinamico deve mantenersi nel tempo, anche al variare delle condizioni esterne, attraverso precisi meccanismi autoregolatori. Per estensione, il termine indica anche la capacità...
Lake in central New York state, US Cayuga LakeCayuga Lake as viewed in the late afternoon from Cornell University in November 2005Cayuga LakeLocation of Cayuga Lake in New York stateShow map of New York Adirondack ParkCayuga LakeCayuga Lake (the United States)Show map of the United StatesLocationCayuga / Seneca / Tompkins counties, New York, U.S.GroupFinger LakesCoordinates42°41′17″N 76°42′8″W / 42.68806°N 76.70222°W / 42.68806; -76.70222Lake typeGround mor...
Men's Greco-Roman 57 kgat the Games of the XIX OlympiadVenueInsurgentes Ice RinkDates23–26 OctoberCompetitors24 from 24 nationsMedalists János Varga Hungary Ion Baciu Romania Ivan Kochergin Soviet Union← 19641972 → Wrestling at the1968 Summer OlympicsFreestyleFlyweightmenBantamweightmenFeatherweightmenLightweightmenWelterweightmenMiddleweightmenLight heavyweightmenHeavyweightmenGreco-RomanFlyweightmenBantamweightmenFeatherweightmenLightwei...
Ignoto napoletano, Ritratto di Nicola Antonio Porpora, Bologna, Museo internazionale e biblioteca della musica Nicola Antonio Giacinto Porpora, talvolta indicato anche come Nicolò o Niccolò (Napoli, 17 agosto 1686 – Napoli, 3 marzo 1768), è stato un compositore e maestro di canto italiano. Fu uno dei più celebri compositori della sua epoca soprattutto per quanto riguarda l'ambito operistico. Indice 1 Biografia 1.1 A Roma per Berenice 1.2 Imeneo per Farinelli 1.3 Alla corte di Sassonia 1...
يفتقر محتوى هذه المقالة إلى الاستشهاد بمصادر. فضلاً، ساهم في تطوير هذه المقالة من خلال إضافة مصادر موثوق بها. أي معلومات غير موثقة يمكن التشكيك بها وإزالتها. (يناير 2022) الدائرة الكهربائية التي توصل مكوناتها على التوالي، أي يمر فيها التيار واحدة تلو الأخرى تسمى دارة التوالي ...
Town in Afar Region, Ethiopia Town in Afar Region, EthiopiaAysaqiitaTownAsaitaMotto: Aysaqiiti Magaalah XiinissoAysaqiitaLocation within EthiopiaShow map of EthiopiaAysaqiitaLocation within the Horn of AfricaShow map of Horn of AfricaAysaqiitaLocation within AfricaShow map of AfricaCoordinates: 11°34′N 41°26′E / 11.567°N 41.433°E / 11.567; 41.433Country EthiopiaRegionAfar RegionZoneAwsi RasuNamed forAysa'eeta meaning foundation or meaning just leave o...
This article needs additional citations for verification. Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources. Unsourced material may be challenged and removed.Find sources: Military ranks of East Germany – news · newspapers · books · scholar · JSTOR (June 2017) (Learn how and when to remove this message) The Ranks of the National People's Army were the military insignia used by the National People's Army, the army of the German D...