A precursor to second-order arithmetic that involves third-order parameters was introduced by David Hilbert and Paul Bernays in their book Grundlagen der Mathematik.[1] The standard axiomatization of second-order arithmetic is denoted by Z2.
Second-order arithmetic includes, but is significantly stronger than, its first-order counterpart Peano arithmetic. Unlike Peano arithmetic, second-order arithmetic allows quantification over sets of natural numbers as well as numbers themselves. Because real numbers can be represented as (infinite) sets of natural numbers in well-known ways, and because second-order arithmetic allows quantification over such sets, it is possible to formalize the real numbers in second-order arithmetic. For this reason, second-order arithmetic is sometimes called "analysis".[2]
Second-order arithmetic can also be seen as a weak version of set theory in which every element is either a natural number or a set of natural numbers. Although it is much weaker than Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, second-order arithmetic can prove essentially all of the results of classical mathematics expressible in its language.
A subsystem of second-order arithmetic is a theory in the language of second-order arithmetic each axiom of which is a theorem of full second-order arithmetic (Z2). Such subsystems are essential to reverse mathematics, a research program investigating how much of classical mathematics can be derived in certain weak subsystems of varying strength. Much of core mathematics can be formalized in these weak subsystems, some of which are defined below. Reverse mathematics also clarifies the extent and manner in which classical mathematics is nonconstructive.
Definition
Syntax
The language of second-order arithmetic is two-sorted. The first sort of terms and in particular variables, usually denoted by lower case letters, consists of individuals, whose intended interpretation is as natural numbers. The other sort of variables, variously called "set variables", "class variables", or even "predicates" are usually denoted by upper-case letters. They refer to classes/predicates/properties of individuals, and so can be thought of as sets of natural numbers. Both individuals and set variables can be quantified universally or existentially. A formula with no bound set variables (that is, no quantifiers over set variables) is called arithmetical. An arithmetical formula may have free set variables and bound individual variables.
Individual terms are formed from the constant 0, the unary function S (the successor function), and the binary operations + and (addition and multiplication). The successor function adds 1 to its input. The relations = (equality) and < (comparison of natural numbers) relate two individuals, whereas the relation ∈ (membership) relates an individual and a set (or class). Thus in notation the language of second-order arithmetic is given by the signature .
For example, , is a well-formed formula of second-order arithmetic that is arithmetical, has one free set variable X and one bound individual variable n (but no bound set variables, as is required of an arithmetical formula)—whereas is a well-formed formula that is not arithmetical, having one bound set variable X and one bound individual variable n.
Semantics
Several different interpretations of the quantifiers are possible. If second-order arithmetic is studied using the full semantics of second-order logic then the set quantifiers range over all subsets of the range of the individual variables. If second-order arithmetic is formalized using the semantics of first-order logic (Henkin semantics) then any model includes a domain for the set variables to range over, and this domain may be a proper subset of the full powerset of the domain of individual variables.[3]
If φ(n) is a formula of second-order arithmetic with a free individual variable n and possibly other free individual or set variables (written m1,...,mk and X1,...,Xl), the induction axiom for φ is the axiom:
The (full) second-order induction scheme consists of all instances of this axiom, over all second-order formulas.
One particularly important instance of the induction scheme is when φ is the formula "" expressing the fact that n is a member of X (X being a free set variable): in this case, the induction axiom for φ is
This sentence is called the second-order induction axiom.
If φ(n) is a formula with a free variable n and possibly other free variables, but not the variable Z, the comprehension axiom for φ is the formula
This axiom makes it possible to form the set of natural numbers satisfying φ(n). There is a technical restriction that the formula φ may not contain the variable Z, for otherwise the formula would lead to the comprehension axiom
,
which is inconsistent. This convention is assumed in the remainder of this article.
The full system
The formal theory of second-order arithmetic (in the language of second-order arithmetic) consists of the basic axioms, the comprehension axiom for every formula φ (arithmetic or otherwise), and the second-order induction axiom. This theory is sometimes called full second-order arithmetic to distinguish it from its subsystems, defined below. Because full second-order semantics imply that every possible set exists, the comprehension axioms may be taken to be part of the deductive system when full second-order semantics is employed.[3]
Models
This section describes second-order arithmetic with first-order semantics. Thus a model of the language of second-order arithmetic consists of a set M (which forms the range of individual variables) together with a constant 0 (an element of M), a function S from M to M, two binary operations + and · on M, a binary relation < on M, and a collection D of subsets of M, which is the range of the set variables. Omitting D produces a model of the language of first-order arithmetic.
When D is the full powerset of M, the model is called a full model. The use of full second-order semantics is equivalent to limiting the models of second-order arithmetic to the full models. In fact, the axioms of second-order arithmetic have only one full model. This follows from the fact that the Peano axioms with the second-order induction axiom have only one model under second-order semantics.
Definable functions
The first-order functions that are provably total in second-order arithmetic are precisely the same as those representable in system F.[4] Almost equivalently, system F is the theory of functionals corresponding to second-order arithmetic in a manner parallel to how Gödel's system T corresponds to first-order arithmetic in the Dialectica interpretation.
More types of models
When a model of the language of second-order arithmetic has certain properties, it can also be called these other names:
When M is the usual set of natural numbers with its usual operations, is called an ω-model. In this case, the model may be identified with D, its collection of sets of naturals, because this set is enough to completely determine an ω-model. The unique full -model, which is the usual set of natural numbers with its usual structure and all its subsets, is called the intended or standard model of second-order arithmetic.[5]
A model of the language of second-order arithmetic is called a β-model if , i.e. the Σ11-statements with parameters from that are satisfied by are the same as those satisfied by the full model.[6] Some notions that are absolute with respect to β-models include " encodes a well-order"[7] and " is a tree".[6]
The above result has been extended to the concept of a βn-model for , which has the same definition as the above except is replaced by , i.e. is replaced by .[6] Using this definition β0-models are the same as ω-models.[8]
There are many named subsystems of second-order arithmetic.
A subscript 0 in the name of a subsystem indicates that it includes only
a restricted portion of the full second-order induction scheme.[9] Such a restriction lowers the proof-theoretic strength of the system significantly. For example, the system ACA0 described below is equiconsistent with Peano arithmetic. The corresponding theory ACA, consisting of ACA0 plus the full second-order induction scheme, is stronger than Peano arithmetic.
Arithmetical comprehension
Many of the well-studied subsystems are related to closure properties of models. For example, it can be shown that every ω-model of full second-order arithmetic is closed under Turing jump, but not every ω-model closed under Turing jump is a model of full second-order arithmetic. The subsystem ACA0 includes just enough axioms to capture the notion of closure under Turing jump.
ACA0 is defined as the theory consisting of the basic axioms, the arithmetical comprehension axiom scheme (in other words the comprehension axiom for every arithmetical formula φ) and the ordinary second-order induction axiom. It would be equivalent to also include the entire arithmetical induction axiom scheme, in other words to include the induction axiom for every arithmetical formula φ.
It can be shown that a collection S of subsets of ω determines an ω-model of ACA0 if and only if S is closed under Turing jump, Turing reducibility, and Turing join.[10]
The subscript 0 in ACA0 indicates that not every instance of the induction axiom scheme is included this subsystem. This makes no difference for ω-models, which automatically satisfy every instance of the induction axiom. It is of importance, however, in the study of non-ω-models. The system consisting of ACA0 plus induction for all formulas is sometimes called ACA with no subscript.
The system ACA0 is a conservative extension of first-order arithmetic (or first-order Peano axioms), defined as the basic axioms, plus the first-order induction axiom scheme (for all formulas φ involving no class variables at all, bound or otherwise), in the language of first-order arithmetic (which does not permit class variables at all). In particular it has the same proof-theoretic ordinalε0 as first-order arithmetic, owing to the limited induction schema.
A formula is called bounded arithmetical, or Δ00, when all its quantifiers are of the form ∀n<t or ∃n<t (where n is the individual variable being quantified and t is an individual term), where
stands for
and
stands for
.
A formula is called Σ01 (or sometimes Σ1), respectively Π01 (or sometimes Π1) when it is of the form ∃mφ, respectively ∀mφ where φ is a bounded arithmetical formula and m is an individual variable (that is free in φ). More generally, a formula is called Σ0n, respectively Π0n when it is obtained by adding existential, respectively universal, individual quantifiers to a Π0n−1, respectively Σ0n−1 formula (and Σ00 and Π00 are both equal to Δ00). By construction, all these formulas are arithmetical (no class variables are ever bound) and, in fact, by putting the formula in Skolem prenex form one can see that every arithmetical formula is logically equivalent to a Σ0n or Π0n formula for all large enough n.
Recursive comprehension
The subsystem RCA0 is a weaker system than ACA0 and is often used as the base system in reverse mathematics. It consists of: the basic axioms, the Σ01 induction scheme, and the Δ01 comprehension scheme. The former term is clear: the Σ01 induction scheme is the induction axiom for every Σ01 formula φ. The term "Δ01 comprehension" is more complex, because there is no such thing as a Δ01 formula. The Δ01 comprehension scheme instead asserts the comprehension axiom for every Σ01 formula that is logically equivalent to a Π01 formula. This scheme includes, for every Σ01 formula φ and every Π01 formula ψ, the axiom:
The set of first-order consequences of RCA0 is the same as those of the subsystem IΣ1 of Peano arithmetic in which induction is restricted to Σ01 formulas. In turn, IΣ1 is conservative over primitive recursive arithmetic (PRA) for sentences. Moreover, the proof-theoretic ordinal of is ωω, the same as that of PRA.
It can be seen that a collection S of subsets of ω determines an ω-model of RCA0 if and only if S is closed under Turing reducibility and Turing join. In particular, the collection of all computable subsets of ω gives an ω-model of RCA0. This is the motivation behind the name of this system—if a set can be proved to exist using RCA0, then the set is recursive (i.e. computable).
Weaker systems
Sometimes an even weaker system than RCA0 is desired. One such system is defined as follows: one must first augment the language of arithmetic with an exponential function symbol (in stronger systems the exponential can be defined in terms of addition and multiplication by the usual trick, but when the system becomes too weak this is no longer possible) and the basic axioms by the obvious axioms defining exponentiation inductively from multiplication; then the system consists of the (enriched) basic axioms, plus Δ01 comprehension, plus Δ00 induction.
Stronger systems
Over ACA0, each formula of second-order arithmetic is equivalent to a Σ1n or Π1n formula for all large enough n. The system Π11-comprehension is the system consisting of the basic axioms, plus the ordinary second-order induction axiom and the comprehension axiom for every (boldface[11]) Π11 formula φ. This is equivalent to Σ11-comprehension (on the other hand, Δ11-comprehension, defined analogously to Δ01-comprehension, is weaker).
Projective determinacy is the assertion that every two-player perfect information game with moves being natural numbers, game length ω and projective payoff set is determined, that is, one of the players has a winning strategy. (The first player wins the game if the play belongs to the payoff set; otherwise, the second player wins.) A set is projective if and only if (as a predicate) it is expressible by a formula in the language of second-order arithmetic, allowing real numbers as parameters, so projective determinacy is expressible as a schema in the language of Z2.
Many natural propositions expressible in the language of second-order arithmetic are independent of Z2 and even ZFC but are provable from projective determinacy. Examples include coanalytic perfect subset property, measurability and the property of Baire for sets, uniformization, etc. Over a weak base theory (such as RCA0), projective determinacy implies comprehension and provides an essentially complete theory of second-order arithmetic — natural statements in the language of Z2 that are independent of Z2 with projective determinacy are hard to find.[12]
ZFC + {there are nWoodin cardinals: n is a natural number} is conservative over Z2 with projective determinacy[citation needed], that is a statement in the language of second-order arithmetic is provable in Z2 with projective determinacy if and only if its translation into the language of set theory is provable in ZFC + {there are n Woodin cardinals: n∈N}.
Coding mathematics
Second-order arithmetic directly formalizes natural numbers and sets of natural numbers. However, it is able to formalize other mathematical objects indirectly via coding techniques, a fact that was first noticed by Weyl.[13] The integers, rational numbers, and real numbers can all be formalized in the subsystem RCA0, along with completeseparablemetric spaces and continuous functions between them.[14]
The research program of reverse mathematics uses these formalizations of mathematics in second-order arithmetic to study the set-existence axioms required to prove mathematical theorems.[15] For example, the intermediate value theorem for functions from the reals to the reals is provable in RCA0,[16] while the Bolzano–Weierstrass theorem is equivalent to ACA0 over RCA0.[17]
The aforementioned coding works well for continuous and total functions, assuming a higher-order base theory plus weak Kőnig's lemma.[18] As perhaps expected, in the case of topology, coding is not without problems.[19]
^ abShapiro, Stewart (1991). Foundations Without Foundationalism: A Case for Second-Order Logic. Oxford Logic Guides. Vol. 17. The Clarendon Press, Oxford University Press, New York. pp. 66, 74–75. ISBN0-19-853391-8. MR1143781.
^Friedman, H. (1976). "Systems of second order arithmetic with restricted induction, I, II". Meeting of the Association for Symbolic Logic. Journal of Symbolic Logic (Abstracts). 41: 557–559. JSTOR2272259.
^Kohlenbach, Ulrich (2002). "Foundational and mathematical uses of higher types". Reflections on the Foundations of Mathematics: Essays in honor of Solomon Feferman, Papers from the symposium held at Stanford University, Stanford, CA, December 11–13, 1998. Lecture Notes in Logic. Vol. 15. Urbana, Illinois: Association for Symbolic Logic. pp. 92–116. ISBN1-56881-169-1. MR1943304.
Yunani Artikel ini adalah bagian dari seri Politik dan KetatanegaraanYunani Undang-Undang Dasar Sejarah Undang-Undang Dasar Hak asasi manusia Eksekutif Kepala negara Presiden (daftar): Katerina Sakellaropoulou Departemen Kepresidenan Pemerintah Perdana Menteri (daftar): Kyriakos Mitsotakis Kabinet: Kyr. Mitsotakis Legislatif Ketua: Konstantinos Tasoulas Presidium Konferensi Presiden Komite Parlemen Daerah pemilihan Pembagian Yudikatif Mahkamah Agung Mahkamah Khusus Mahkamah Perdata dan Pidana...
Azhar Mansor sedang mengemudikan kapal layar yang diberi nama Jalur Gemilang, sesuai dengan nama bendera Malaysia. Datuk Azhar Mansor adalah orang Malaysia pertama yang berhasil mengelilingi dunia dengan berlayar. Mulanya ia merencanakan untuk melakukan pelayaran tersebut dalam waktu kurang dari 100 hari, tetapi ia menghadapi masalah dengan tiang layar yang patah ketika berada di Cape Horn, Amerika Selatan. Namun Datuk Azhar Mansor akhirnya berhasil menempuh seluruh pelayarannya dalam waktu 1...
For information on all Sam Houston State University sports, see Sam Houston State Bearkats. Sam Houston State Bearkats 2023 Sam Houston Bearkats softball teamUniversitySam Houston State UniversityHead coachGarrett ValisConferenceC-USALocationHuntsville, TXHome stadiumBearkat Softball Complex (Capacity: 400)NicknameBearkatsColorsOrange and white[1] NCAA Tournament championsNAIA: 1981NCAA DII: 1982DI NIT: 1993NCAA WCWS appearancesNAIA: 1981NCAA DII: 1982 ...
العلاقات البالاوية الباهاماسية بالاو باهاماس بالاو باهاماس تعديل مصدري - تعديل العلاقات البالاوية الباهاماسية هي العلاقات الثنائية التي تجمع بين بالاو وباهاماس.[1][2][3][4][5] مقارنة بين البلدين هذه مقارنة عامة ومرجعية للدولتين: وجه المق...
Annual rock music festival This article has multiple issues. Please help improve it or discuss these issues on the talk page. (Learn how and when to remove these template messages) This article needs additional citations for verification. Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources. Unsourced material may be challenged and removed.Find sources: Riot Fest – news · newspapers · books · scholar · JSTOR (September 2022) (Learn ...
Disambiguazione – Se stai cercando Santa Maria Maddalena de' Pazzi, al secolo Caterina de' Pazzi, vedi Maria Maddalena de' Pazzi. Caterina de' PazziStemma della famiglia Pazzi NascitaRepubblica di Firenze, 1463 MorteConvento di Monticelli, Repubblica di Firenze, 23 agosto 1490 Venerata daTutte le Chiese che ammettono il culto dei santi BeatificazioneRoma, XVIII secolo, da Papa Benedetto XIV Manuale Caterina de' Pazzi (Repubblica di Firenze, 1463 – Repubblica di Firenze, 23 agosto 14...
Questa voce sull'argomento stagioni delle società calcistiche italiane è solo un abbozzo. Contribuisci a migliorarla secondo le convenzioni di Wikipedia. Segui i suggerimenti del progetto di riferimento. Voce principale: Associazione Calcio Fortitudo Trieste. Associazione Calcio FortitudoStagione 1936-1937Sport calcio Squadra Fortitudo Trieste Allenatore Gianni Godnig Presidente Renato Rostirolla Serie C14º nel girone A della Serie C, retrocessa in Prima Divisione 1935-1936 1937...
Artikel ini sebatang kara, artinya tidak ada artikel lain yang memiliki pranala balik ke halaman ini.Bantulah menambah pranala ke artikel ini dari artikel yang berhubungan atau coba peralatan pencari pranala.Tag ini diberikan pada Desember 2022. Marko Baša Informasi pribadiNama lengkap Marko BašaTanggal lahir 29 Desember 1982 (umur 41)Tempat lahir Trstenik, SFR YugoslaviaTinggi 1,90 m (6 ft 3 in)Posisi bermain BekInformasi klubKlub saat ini LilleNomor 25Karier senior*Tah...
2023 law that permits gender self-identification in Spain You can help expand this article with text translated from the corresponding article in Spanish. (July 2023) Click [show] for important translation instructions. View a machine-translated version of the Spanish article. Machine translation, like DeepL or Google Translate, is a useful starting point for translations, but translators must revise errors as necessary and confirm that the translation is accurate, rather than simply cop...
Uruguayan writer You can help expand this article with text translated from the corresponding article in Spanish. (August 2018) Click [show] for important translation instructions. Machine translation, like DeepL or Google Translate, is a useful starting point for translations, but translators must revise errors as necessary and confirm that the translation is accurate, rather than simply copy-pasting machine-translated text into the English Wikipedia. Consider adding a topic to this tem...
Antimicrobial agent Not to be confused with triclosan or trichloromethane. Triclocarban Names Preferred IUPAC name N-(4-Chlorophenyl)-N′-(3,4-dichlorophenyl)urea Other names Trichlorocarbanilide, TCC, Solubacter, Vivilide Identifiers CAS Number 101-20-2 Y 3D model (JSmol) Interactive image ChEBI CHEBI:48347 Y ChEMBL ChEMBL1076347 Y ChemSpider 7266 Y ECHA InfoCard 100.002.659 PubChem CID 7547 UNII BGG1Y1ED0Y Y CompTox Dashboard (EPA) DTXSID4026214 InChI InChI=1S/C13H...
Artikel ini tidak memiliki referensi atau sumber tepercaya sehingga isinya tidak bisa dipastikan. Tolong bantu perbaiki artikel ini dengan menambahkan referensi yang layak. Tulisan tanpa sumber dapat dipertanyakan dan dihapus sewaktu-waktu.Cari sumber: Setang – berita · surat kabar · buku · cendekiawan · JSTOR Setang adalah bagian dari sepeda yang digunakan untuk mengarahkan atau mengatur kemudi sepeda yang menempel pada fork sepeda, dan juga berfungsi...
American cartoonist (1906–1971) E. Simms CampbellBornElmer Simms Campbell(1906-01-02)January 2, 1906St. Louis, Missouri, U.S.DiedJanuary 27, 1971(1971-01-27) (aged 65)White Plains, New York, U.S.Area(s)CartoonistNotable worksCuties E. Simms Campbell's Cuties (1968) was syndicated by King Features to more than 145 newspapers. Elmer Simms Campbell (January 2, 1906 – January 27, 1971)[1] was an American commercial artist best known as the cartoonist who signed his work, E. Simms...
Glacier in Alberta and British Columbia, Canada Wapta GlacierWapta ice fieldsWapta GlacierShow map of AlbertaWapta GlacierShow map of British ColumbiaWapta GlacierShow map of CanadaLocationAlberta, CanadaCoordinates51°38′22″N 116°31′35″W / 51.63944°N 116.52639°W / 51.63944; -116.52639StatusReceding The Wapta Icefield from Mistaya Mountain The Wapta Icefield is a series of glaciers located on the Continental Divide in the Waputik Mountains of the Canadian Ro...
NS-74 Tren de rodadura neumática Tren NS-74 entre Toesca y Parque O'Higgins (Línea 2)Datos generalesFabricante Alsthom Groupe BrissonneauAño fabricación 1972-1981Unidades fabricadas 49 trenes (245 unidades) 24 trenes en servicio (168 unidades)[1][2]Matriculación nacional 3001 a 3049Servicios PasajerosOperador Metro de SantiagoCaracterísticas técnicasTipo de tracción EléctricaDisposición de ejes B'B' (coches M y N) 2'2' (coches P y R)Ancho de vía 1435 mmComposición 5 ...