Skeptical theism is the view that people should remain skeptical of their ability to discern whether their perceptions about evil can be considered good evidence against the existence of the orthodox Christian God.[1] The central thesis of skeptical theism is that it would not be surprising for an infinitely intelligent and knowledgeable being's reasons for permitting evils to be beyond human comprehension.[2] That is, what may seem like pointless evils may be necessary for a greater good or to prevent equal or even greater evils. This central thesis may be argued from a theistic perspective, but is also argued to defend positions of agnosticism.[3][4]
Skeptical theism can be an informally held belief based on theistic doctrine,[5] but the origin of the term skeptical theist is the 1996 paper "The Skeptical Theist" by philosopher Paul Draper.[6][7] Following Draper's publication, the term skeptical theism was adopted in academic philosophy and has developed into a family of positions supporting skeptical theism's central skeptical thesis; we should remain skeptical of claims that human beings can discern God's reasons for evils. One argument is based on analogy, likening our understanding of God's motives to those of a child grasping a parent's reasons for seeking painful medical treatment, for example. Other approaches are the limitations on the human ability to understand the moral realm, and appeals to epistemic factors such as sensitivity or contextual requirements.[8]
In the philosophy of religion, skeptical theism is not a broad skepticism toward human knowledge of God, but is instead putatively presented as a response to philosophical propositions, such as those focused on drawing "all things considered" inductive conclusions about God's motives from perceived circumstances.[9] Additionally, skeptical theism is not a position used to defend all forms of theism, though it is most often presented in the defense of orthodox Christian theism. Moreover, skeptical theism is not supported by all theists and some who support its skeptical positions are not theists.[6][10]
In philosophy, skeptical theism is a defense of theistic or agnostic positions[11] argued to undercut a crucial premise in atheologicalarguments from evil, a claim that God could have no good reasons for allowing certain types of evil.[11][12] It is also presented in response to other atheological arguments claiming to know God's purposes based on circumstances, such as the argument from divine hiddenness.[13]
Draper's skeptical theism
In the philosophy of religion, skeptical theism is the position that we should be skeptical of our ability to assess God's motivations or lack of motivation from our perceptions of the circumstances we observe in the world. The view is a response to the atheological argument from evil, which asserts that some evils in the world are gratuitous, pointless, or inscrutable evils, and that they thus represent evidence against the existence of the God of orthodox Christianity. God, by the orthodox view, is thought to be omniscient (all-knowing), omnibenevolent (all-good) and omnipotent (all-powerful).[14][15] Insofar as it tries to reconcile this conception of God with concerns about gratuitous evils (evils that do occur in the world, but which God is argued to have no morally sufficient reason for permitting), skeptical theism can be considered a form of theodicy. As originally proposed by agnostic philosopher Paul Draper, the view is intended to undercut a key premise in the argument from evil by suggesting that human cognitive faculties could be insufficient to permit drawing inductive inferences concerning God's reasons or lack of reasons for permitting perceived evils.[6][16]
The evidential argument from evil
The evidential argument from evil asserts that the amount, types, or distribution of evils, provide an evidential basis for concluding that God's existence is improbable.[17] The argument has a number of formulation, but can be stated in the Modus ponens logical form:
If an omniscient, omnibenevolent and omnipotent God exists, there should be no gratuitous evil.
There exists instances of gratuitous evil.
Therefore, an omniscient, omnibenevolent and omnipotent God does not exist.
In this logical form the conclusion (3) is true, if both the major premise (1) and minor premise (2) are true. Philosophers have challenged both premises, but skeptical theism focuses on the minor premise (2).
In 1979, philosopher William Rowe provided a defense of the minor premise (2). He argued that no state of affairs we know of is such that an omnipotent, omniscient being's obtaining it would morally justify that being's permitting some instances of horrific suffering. Therefore, Rowe concludes, it is likely that no state of affairs exists that would morally justify that being in permitting such suffering.[18] In other words, Rowe argues that his inability to think of a good reason why God would allow a particular evil justifies the conclusion that there is no such reason, and the conclusion that God does not exist.
The "noseeum" inference
The philosophers Michael Bergmann and Michael Rea described William Rowe's justification for the second premise of the argument from evil:
Some evidential arguments from evil ... rely on a "noseeum" inference of the following sort: NI: If, after thinking hard, we can't think of any God-justifying reason for permitting some horrific evil then it is likely that there is no such reason. (The reason NI is called a 'noseeum' inference is that it says, more or less, that because we don't see 'um, they probably ain't there.)[18][19][20][21]
Various analogies are offered to show that the noseeum inference is logically dubious. For example, a novice chess player's inability to discern a chess master's choice of moves cannot be used to infer that there is no good reason for the move.[11]
The skeptical theist's response
Skeptical theism provides a defense against the evidential argument from evil, but does not take a position on God's actual reason for allowing a particular instance of evil. The defense seeks to show that there are good reasons to believe that God could have justified reasons for allowing a particular evil that we cannot discern. Consequently, we are in no position to endorse the minor premise (2) of the argument from evil because we cannot be more than agnostic about the accuracy of the premise. This conclusion would be an undercutting defeater for the premise because there would be no justification for the conclusion that evils in our world are gratuitous. To justify this conclusion, the skeptical theist argues that the limits of human cognitive faculties are grounds for skepticism about our ability to draw conclusions about God's motives or lack of motives; it is therefore reasonable to doubt the second premise.[22] Bergmann and Rea thus concluded that Rowe's inference is unsound.[23]
References
^McBrayer, Justin (2015). "Sceptical theism". The Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved October 10, 2016. Sceptical theists are ... sceptical of our abilities to discern whether the evils in our world constitute good evidence against the existence of God. For a state of the art discussion of its merits and drawbacks, see Benton, Matthew A.; Hawthorne, John; Isaacs, Yoaav (2016). "Evil and Evidence"(PDF). Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion. 7: 1–31. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198757702.003.0001. ISBN978-0-19-875770-2..
^"Skeptical Theism". Internet Dictionary of Philosophy. Retrieved October 10, 2016. In particular, says the skeptical theist, we should not grant that our inability to think of a good reason for doing or allowing something is indicative of whether or not God might have a good reason for doing or allowing something.
^"Skeptical theism". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. January 25, 2014. Retrieved October 13, 2016. Alston is not quite as explicit, but seems to agree. He calls the position he defends "agnosticism" (1996, 98). He says that our cognitive resources are "radically insufficient to provide sufficient warrant to accepting [the main premise of the evidential argument]," so much so that "the inductive argument collapses"
^Alston, William (1996). Howard-Snyder, Daniel (ed.). Some (temporarily) Final Thoughts on Evidential Arguments from Evil (in The Evidential Argument from Evil, ed Howard-Snyder). Indiana: Indiana University Press. pp. 98 (article), 311–332 (book).
^Book of Isaiah 55:8 (New Living Translation). My thoughts are nothing like your thoughts," says the Lord. "And my ways are far beyond anything you could imagine
^McBrayer, Justin (2015). "Sceptical theism". Skeptical Theism. Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. doi:10.4324/9780415249126-K3583-1. ISBN9780415250696. Retrieved October 13, 2016. Contemporary philosophers have further refined sceptical theism into a family of related views, each with a different defence. These defences include appeals to analogies (for example the parent/child relationship), appeals to the limitations of our grasp of the moral realm and appeals to epistemic requirements (for example sensitivity requirements or contextual requirements).
^McBrayer, Justin P. "Skeptical Theism". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. It is important to get clear on the scope of the skepticism endorsed by skeptical theists. First, it is not a global skepticism—skeptical theists are not committed to the view that we cannot know anything at all. Instead, the skepticism is (putatively) limited to a narrow range of propositions, namely those having to do with God's reasons for action. For example, a skeptical theist could admit that humans have ceteris paribus knowledge of God's reasons for actions. An example of such knowledge might be the following: other-things-being-equal, God will eliminate suffering when he is able to do so. However, knowing this latter claim is consistent with denying that we know the following: God will eliminate this particular instance of suffering. Holding the combination of these two views is possible for the following reason: while we might know that other-things-being-equal, God will eliminate suffering when he is able to do so, we might not know whether or not other things are equal in any particular instance of suffering.
^McBrayer, Justine. "Skeptical Theism". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved October 9, 2016. Not all theists are skeptical theists, and not all of the philosophers who endorse the skeptical component of skeptical theism are theists.
^"Skeptical Theism". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved October 13, 2016. If skeptical theism is true, it appears to undercut the primary argument for atheism, namely the argument from evil. This is because skeptical theism provides a reason to be skeptical of a crucial premise in the argument from evil, namely the premise that asserts that at least some of the evils in our world are gratuitous.
^McBrayer, Justin (2015). "Sceptical theism". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved October 10, 2016. The sceptical element of sceptical theism can be used to undermine various arguments for atheism including both the argument from evil and the argument from divine hiddenness.
^"Skeptical Theism". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. January 25, 2014. Retrieved October 9, 2016.
^"The Evidential Problem of Evil". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved October 11, 2016. Evidential arguments from evil attempt to show that, once we put aside any evidence there might be in support of the existence of God, it becomes unlikely, if not highly unlikely, that the world was created and is governed by an omnipotent, omniscient, and wholly good being.
^McBrayer, Justin (2015). "Sceptical Theism". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. doi:10.4324/9780415249126-K3583-1. ISBN9780415250696. Retrieved October 10, 2016. According to sceptical theists, the human mind is limited in such a way that it would not at all be surprising that God would have reasons that are beyond our understanding for allowing the evils of our world.