Practice of refusing some, but not all, military service
Selective conscientious objection is the practice of refusing some, but not all, military service. It is much more controversial than blanket conscientious objection based on consistent pacifism.[1] Views on selective conscientious objection range from being morally impermissible, morally permissible, a right that may be exercised, or morally obligatory in the case of military personnel asked to fight an illegal war of aggression.[2]
Arguments for and against
The traditional view is that soldiers are obligated to obey superior orders to participate in a war, even when this is against their conscience.[1] The moral culpability for fighting an unjust war, in this view, is visited entirely on the leaders and not on ordinary soldiers who are entirely innocent (see moral equality of combatants).[1][3] Arguments for this view include those based on social contract theory which posit that citizens should obey their state's decision to go to war, the argument that individual soldiers are ill-placed to determine whether a war is just.[1]
If the war seems patently unjust to the subject, he must not fight, even if he is ordered to do so by the prince. This is obvious, since one may not lawfully kill an innocent man on any authority, and in the case we are speaking of the enemy must be innocent. . . if their conscience tells subjects that the war is unjust, they must not go to war even if this conscience is wrong.[1]
Those who reject the moral equality of combatants regardless of whether they are fighting for a just or unjust cause argue that individual soldiers have an obligation to refuse to fight an unjust war if they can do so without suffering death or other grave harms.[4]John Rawls argues that selective objection should be allowed as it may prevent the government from continuing an unjust war.[5]
Legally, courts in most countries have distinguished between blanket objection and selective objection, allowing only the former.[1][5] Soldiers have a right and a responsibility to refuse to commit war crimes, but the right to refuse to fight an illegal war is not widely recognized.[8] In the United States, the 1971 Gillette v. United States found that to be recognized as a conscientious objector, one must refuse all wars.[9] International law scholar Tom Dannenbaum argues that soldiers should have a right not to fight in illegal wars, and those who refuse to should be recognized as refugees.[10]
References
^ abcdefRobinson, Paul (2015). "Selective Conscientious Objection". Routledge Handbook of Military Ethics. Routledge. ISBN978-1-315-81351-6.
^Syse, Henrik (2015). "The Moral Equality of Combatants". The Ashgate Research Companion to Military Ethics. Routledge. p. 261. ISBN978-1-315-61324-6.
^ abcPaz-Fuchs, Amir; Sfard, Michael (2002). "The Fallacies of Objections to Selective Conscientious Objection". Israel Law Review. 36 (3): 111–143. doi:10.1017/S0021223700017994. S2CID142864016.
^Cajka, Peter (2021). Follow Your Conscience: The Catholic Church and the Spirit of the Sixties. University of Chicago Press. pp. 68–69. ISBN978-0-226-76219-7.