One of the main goals of this extended calculus is to be able to describe expressions corresponding to theorems in classical logic. According to the Curry–Howard isomorphism, lambda calculus on its own can express theorems in intuitionistic logic only, and several classical logical theorems can't be written at all. However with these new operators one is able to write terms that have the type of, for example, Peirce's law.
The μ operator corresponds to Felleisen's undelimited control operator C and bracket corresponds to calling a captured continuation.[2]
Formal definition
The three forms of expressions in lambda calculus are as follows:
An abstractionλx. M, where x is any identifier and M is any lambda expression.
An application(M N), where M and N are any lambda expressions.
In addition to the traditional λ-variables, the lambda-mu calculus includes a distinct set of μ-variables, which can be understood as continuation variables. The set of terms is divided into unnamed (all traditional lambda expressions are of this kind) and named terms. The terms that are added by the lambda-mu calculus are of the form:
[α]M is a named term, where α is a μ-variable and M is an unnamed term.
(μ α. t) is an unnamed term, where α is a μ-variable and t is a named term.
Reduction
The basic reduction rules used in the lambda-mu calculus are the following:
beta reduction
structural reduction
, where the substitutions are to be made for all subterms of of the form .
To obtain call-by-value semantics, one must refine the beta reduction rule and add another form of structural reduction:[3]
call-by-value beta reduction
, where V is a value
right structural reduction
, where V is a value
This addition corresponds to the addition of an additional evaluation context former when moving from call-by-name to call-by-value evaluation.
De Groote's unstratified syntax
For a closer correspondence with conventional formalizations of control operators, the distinction between named and unnamed terms can be abolished, meaning that [α]M is of the same sort as other lambda-expressions and the body of μ-abstraction can also be any expression.[2] Another variant in this vein is the Λμ-calculus.[4]
Symmetric lambda-mu calculus
One can consider a structural reduction rule symmetric to the original one:[1]
This, however, breaks confluence and the correspondence to control operators.
See also
Classical pure type systems for typed generalizations of lambda calculi with control
References
^ abMichel Parigot (1992). λμ-Calculus: An algorithmic interpretation of classical natural deduction. Lecture Notes in Computer Science. Vol. 624. pp. 190–201. doi:10.1007/BFb0013061. ISBN3-540-55727-X.