Discourse ethics

Discourse ethics refers to a type of argument that attempts to establish normative or ethical truths by examining the presuppositions of discourse.[1] The ethical theory originated with German philosophers Jürgen Habermas and Karl-Otto Apel, and variations have been used by Frank Van Dun and Habermas' student Hans-Hermann Hoppe.[2]

Habermas and Apel

Habermas's discourse ethics is his attempt to explain the implications of communicative rationality in the sphere of moral insight and normative validity. It is a complex theoretical effort to reformulate the fundamental insights of Kantian deontological ethics in terms of the analysis of communicative structures. This means that it is an attempt to explain the universal and obligatory nature of morality by evoking the universal obligations of communicative rationality. It is also a cognitivist moral theory, which means it holds that justifying the validity of moral norms can be done in a manner analogous to the justification of facts. However, the entire project is undertaken as a rational reconstruction of moral insight. It claims only to reconstruct the implicit normative orientations that guide individuals and it claims to access these through an analysis of communication.

Public discourse ethics

This type of ethics consists of conversations about ideas in civic or community contexts marked by diversity of perspectives requiring thoughtful public engagement. This discourse is made up of differing insights that helps to shape the public's engagement with one another.[3] This type of discourse is meant to protect and to promote the public good. For public discourse ethics to be successful there must be an effective level of civility between people or persons involved. It was Sigmund Freud who once said, "civilization began the first time an angry person cast a word instead of a rock" and that statement is something that continues to be seen in society today.[4] The Harvard Law Review accurately examines public discourse and explains it in a manner that is appropriate and conceptually accurate. "Every man who publishes a book commits himself to the judgement of the public, and anyone may comment upon his performance.... [W]hatever their merits, others have a right to pass their judgement upon them-to censure them if they be censurable, and to turn them into ridicule if they be ridiculous".[5] For the public discourse ethics to be productive there must be accountability on the public stage as the Harvard Law Review calls into question. Without any act of accountability the ethicality of the discourse is no longer valid and cannot go on. Public accountability consists of three basic factors. The factors are:

  • a diversity of ideas,
  • an engagement of public decision making, and finally
  • an account for continuing a practice or way of doing something or a means or reason for changing the practice.

Finally, public discourse ethics puts a great responsibility on the individual. They must continually be asking questions and finding answers. They will not always be right, and that is okay, as long as they are able to make a positive decision in the end.

Presupposition

Habermas maintains that normative validity cannot be understood as separate from the argumentative procedures used in everyday practice, such as those used to resolve issues concerning the legitimacy of actions and the validity of the norms governing interactions. He makes this claim by making reference to the validity dimensions attached to speech acts in communication and the implicit forms of argumentation they imply (see Universal pragmatics). The basic idea is that the validity of a moral norm cannot be justified in the mind of an isolated individual reflecting on the world. The validity of a norm is justified only intersubjectively in processes of argumentation between individuals; in a dialectic. The validity of a claim to normative rightness depends upon the mutual understanding achieved by individuals in argument.

From this it follows that the presuppositions of argumentation would become important. Kant extracted moral principles from the necessities forced upon a rational subject reflecting on the world. Habermas extracts moral principles from the necessities forced upon individuals engaged in the discursive justification of validity claims, from the inescapable presuppositions of communication and argumentation. These presuppositions were the kinds of idealization that individuals had to make in order for communication and argumentation to even begin. For example:

  • The presupposition that participants in communicative exchange are using the same linguistic expressions in the same way
  • The presupposition that no relevant argument is suppressed or excluded by the participants
  • The presupposition that no force except that of the better argument is exerted
  • The presupposition that all the participants are motivated only by a concern for the better argument

There were also presuppositions unique to discourse:

  • The presupposition that everyone would agree to the universal validity of the claim thematized
  • The presupposition that everyone capable of speech and action is entitled to participate, and everyone is equally entitled to introduce new topics or express attitudes needs or desires
  • The presupposition that no validity claim is exempt in principle from critical evaluation in argumentation

These are all at the center of Habermas's moral theory. Habermas's discourse ethics attempts to distill the idealized moral point of view that accompanies a perfectly rational process of argumentation (also idealized), which would be the moral principle implied by the presuppositions listed above. The key point is that the presuppositions of argumentation and communication that have been rationally reconstructed by Habermas are both factual and normative. This can be said about his entire project because it is explicitly attempting to bridge the gap between the "is" and the "ought." Habermas speaks of the mutual recognition and exchanging of roles and perspectives that are demanded by the very structural condition of rational argumentation. He maintains that what is implied in these factual presuppositions of communication is the deep structure of moral norms, the conditions that every valid norm must fulfill.

Universalization

The presuppositions of communication express a universal obligation to maintain impartial judgment in discourse, which constrains all affected to adopt the perspectives of all others in the exchange of reasons. From this Habermas extracts the following principle of universalization (U), which is the condition every valid norm has to fulfill:

(U) All affected can accept the consequences and the side effects that [the norm's] general observance can be anticipated to have for the satisfaction of everyone's interests, and the consequences are preferred to those of known alternative possibilities for regulation. (Habermas, 1991:65)

This can be understood as the deep structure of all acceptable moral norms, and should not be confused with the principle of discourse ethics (D), which presupposes that norms exist that satisfy the conditions specified by (U).

(D) Only those norms can claim to be valid that meet (or could meet) with the approval of all affected in their capacity as participants in a practical discourse.

The implications of (U) and (D) are quite profound. (U) claims to be a rational reconstruction of the impartial moral point of view at the heart of all cognitivist moral theories. According to moral cognitivists (e.g. Kant, Rawls etc.), it is only from such a moral point of view that insight into the actual (quasi-factual) impersonal obligations of a general will can be gained, because this perspective relieves decisions from the inaccuracies of personal interests. Of course, Habermas's reconstruction is different because it is intersubjective. That is, Habermas (unlike Kant or Rawls) formulates the moral point of view as it arises out of the multiple perspectives of those affected by a norm under consideration. The moral point of view explicated in (U) is not the property of an individual subject but the property of a community of interlocutors, the results of a complex dialogical process of role taking and perspective exchanging. Furthermore, (U) is deduced from a rational reconstruction of the presupposition of communication, which downgrades the strong transcendentalism of Kantian ethics by establishing a foundation in inner-worldly processes of communication.

(D) on the other hand is a principle concerning the manner in which norms conforming to (U) must be justified through discourse. Again, Habermas takes the task of moral reflection out of the isolated individual's head and gives it to intersubjective processes of communication. What (D) proposes is that moral principles must be validated in actual discourse and that those to be affected by a norm must be able to participate in argumentation concerning its validity. No number of thought experiments can replace a communicative exchange with others regarding moral norms that will affect them. Moreover, this general prescription concerning the type of discourse necessary for the justification of moral norms opens the process of moral deliberation to the kind of learning that accompanies a fallibilistic orientation. (U) and (D) are catalysts for a moral learning process, which although fallible is not relative. The flesh and blood insights of participants in communicative exchange are refracted through the universal guidelines explicated from the deep structures of communication and argumentation. This spawns discourses with a rational trajectory, which are grounded in the particular circumstances of those involved but aimed at a universal moral validity.

Practical applications

The practical applications of discourse ethics have taken a significant turn after the publication of Habermas' book Between Facts and Norms (1992),[6] where its application to democracy and the legislative process was substantially refined and expanded. Before this book, Habermas had left open the question of the various applications of discourse theory to almost any type of consensus oriented group[7] ranging from highly visible political and governmental groups, such as Parliament in Great Britain and Congressional debate in the United States, and other consensus oriented activities as found in public and private institutions such as those supported on various international websites and Wikipedia.[third-party source needed]

See also

References

  1. ^ "Discourse Ethics". Encyclopedia.com.
  2. ^ Àbba, Giuseppe (1996). Quale Impostazione per la filosofia morale?. Roma: LAS. pp. 126–128. ISBN 978-88-213-0314-2.
  3. ^ Arnett, Ronald C.; Fritz, Janie; Bell, Leeanne Marian (2009). Communication ethics Literacy. California: SAGE Publications Inc. pp. 99–115. ISBN 978-1-4129-4214-0.
  4. ^ Waisanen, D. "TOWARD ROBUST PUBLIC ENGAGEMENT:THE VALUE OF DELIBERATIVE DISCOURSE FOR CIVIL COMMUNICATION". pp. 287–288.
  5. ^ Post, Robert (1990). "Harvard Law Review". p. 627.
  6. ^ Habermas, Jurgen (1995). Between Facts and Norms. Cambridge: MIT Press.
  7. ^ Habermas, Jurgen (1986). Moral Consciousness and Communicative Ethics. Cambridge: MIT Press.

Further reading

  • Habermas, Jürgen (1983). Discourse Ethics: Notes on a Program of Philosophical Justification.
  • Habermas, Jürgen (1991). Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action. Cambridge: MIT Press. ISBN 978-0-262-58118-9.
  • Benhabi, Seyla; Fred Reinhard Dallmayr (1990). "Is the Ethics of the Ideal Communication Community a Utopia?". The Communicative Ethics Controversy. Karl-Otto Apel. MIT Press. ISBN 978-0-262-52152-9.
  • Calhoun, C. 1992 ed., Habermas and the Public Sphere (Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press).
  • Chevigny, Paul G. (1982). "The Dialogic Right of Free Expression: A Reply to Michael Martin". New York University Law Review. 57: 920–931.
  • Chevigny, Paul G. (1980). "Philosophy of Language and Free Expression". New York University Law Review. 55: 157–194.
  • Cohen, J.L., 1995, “Critical Social Theory and Feminist Critiques: The Debate with Jürgen Habermas,” in Johanna Meehan, ed., Feminists Read Habermas: Gendering the Subject of Discourse (New York: Routledge), pp. 57–90.
  • Eley, G., 1992, “Nations, Publics, and Political Cultures: Placing Habermas in the Nineteenth Century,” in Craig Calhoun, ed., Habermas and the Public Sphere (Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press), pp. 289–339.
  • Foucault, M., 1988, “The Ethic of Care for the Self as a Practice of Freedom,” in James Bernauer and David Rasmussen, eds., The Final Foucault (Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press), pp. 1–20.
  • Fraser, N., 1987, “What’s Critical About Critical Theory? The Case of Habermas and Gender,” in Seyla Benhabib and Drucilla Cornell, eds., Feminism as Critique: On the Politics of Gender (Cambridge: Polity Press), pp. 31–56.
  • Gewirth, Alan (1978). Reason and Morality. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0-226-28876-5.
  • Gewirth, Alan. "The Basis and Content of Human Rights". Georgia Law Review. 13: 1148.
  • Stephan Kinsella, Argumentation Ethics and Liberty: A Concise Guide
  • Martin, Michael (1982). "On a New Argument for Freedom of Speech". New York University Law Review. 57: 906–919.
  • Ryan, M.P., 1992, “Gender and Public Access: Women’s Politics in Nineteenth-Century America,” in Craig Calhoun, ed., Habermas and the Public Sphere (Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press), pp. 259–288.
  • Shearmur, Jeremy (1990). "From Dialogue Rights to Property Rights: Foundations for Hayek's Legal Theory". Critical Review. 4 (1–2): 106–32. doi:10.1080/08913819008459596.
  • Shearmur, Jeremy (1988). "Habermas: A Critical Approach". Critical Review. 2: 39–50. doi:10.1080/08913818908459512.
  • Shearmur, Jeremy (1996). The Political Thought of Karl Popper. Routledge. ISBN 978-0-415-09726-0.
  • Shearmur, Jeremy (1996). Hayek and After. Routledge. ISBN 978-0-415-14058-4.
  • "Comment on R.P.Murphy's & Gene Callahan's Critique of Hans-Hermann Hoppe's Argumentation" (PDF). Archived from the original (PDF) on March 7, 2008.

Read other articles:

Blade element theory (BET) is a mathematical process originally designed by William Froude (1878),[1] David W. Taylor (1893) and Stefan Drzewiecki (1885) to determine the behavior of propellers. It involves breaking a blade down into several small parts then determining the forces on each of these small blade elements. These forces are then integrated along the entire blade and over one rotor revolution in order to obtain the forces and moments produced by the entire propeller or roto...

Death toll (50 fatalities or more) Table key Table key (deaths, type) Column Abbreviation Definition Deaths Tot Total C Crew P Passenger G Ground N Notes † No survivors ‡ No occupants 1* Sole survivor Tabv.forType COM Commercial (accident/incident) MIL Military (accident/incident) INB Bombing INH Hijacking EXG Attacked using ground-based weapons EXS Attacked by other aircraft Table key (location, phase of flight) Column Abbreviation Definition Location (none) < 20 km (12.5 mi...

Борошняне масло Борошняне масло (масло «маньє»[1], бер маньє́[2], фр. beurre manié) — кулінарний напівфабрикат, вершкове масло, перетерте з борошном приблизно в рівних кількостях. Винахід французької кухні, застосовується для швидкого загущування[3] гарячих соусі...

Mario Agodino Información personalNacimiento 1917 San Francisco (Argentina) Fallecimiento 1975 Nacionalidad ArgentinaInformación profesionalOcupación Abogado y político Cargos ocupados Gobernador de la provincia de Córdoba Partido político Partido Justicialista [editar datos en Wikidata] Mario Dante Agodino (San Francisco, Córdoba, 1917 - 1975) fue un político argentino, integrante del Partido Justicialista, abogado, miembro fundador del Colegio de Abogados de la Quinta Circ...

  لمعانٍ أخرى، طالع النصب (توضيح). قرية النصب  - قرية -  تقسيم إداري البلد  اليمن المحافظة محافظة حجة المديرية مديرية وشحة العزلة عزلة ضاعن السكان التعداد السكاني 2004 السكان 858   • الذكور 475   • الإناث 383   • عدد الأسر 47   • عدد المساكن 44 معلومات أخرى ال

Functional department of the Central Committee of the Chinese Communist Party United Front Work Department中共中央统一战线工作部UFWD headquartersFormation1942; 81 years ago (1942)TypeDepartment directly reporting to the Central Committee of the Chinese Communist PartyHeadquarters135 Fuyou Street, Xicheng District, BeijingHeadShi TaifengExecutive deputy headChen Xiaojiang*Deputy headsPan Yue*, Xu Lejiang*, Shi Jun, Cui MaohuDiscipline SecretaryLiu JunchuanParent or...

Canadian actor and filmmaker Fawzia MirzaBornFawzia MirzaEducationChicago-Kent College of LawIndiana University BloomingtonOccupation(s)Director, Writer, Producer, ActorYears active2006-PresentKnown forWriting, Filmmaking, Queer Muslim AdvocateNotable workSignature Move, The Red Line, Noor & Layla, Me My Mom & Sharmila Fawzia Mirza is a Canadian film and TV actress, writer, producer, and director. Her work includes web series Kam Kardashian and Brown Girl Problems, and the 2...

Aerial starboard side view of the U.S. cargo vessel Admiral Halstead. (Australian War Memorial) History Name Suwordenco Admiral Halstead Owner Submarine Boat Corporation (1922—1930) Pacific Steamship Company (1930-1936) Pacific Lighterage Company (1936-1947) Pacific Mail Steamship Company (1947-1949) Operator Transmarine (1922—1930) Pacific Steamship Company (1930-1936) Pacific Lighterage (1936-1947) Pacific Mail Steamship Company (1947-1949) Port of registryNew York, New York BuilderSubm...

ABBA discographyABBA in April 1974Studio albums9Live albums2Compilation albums7Video albums5Music videos42Singles50Additional compilations20Non-English releases2Box sets4 The discography of Swedish pop music group ABBA consists of nine studio albums, two live albums, seven compilation albums, four box sets, five video albums, 50 singles, and 43 music videos. To date, ABBA has sold 150 million records worldwide[1] becoming one of the best-selling music artists in history. They have sco...

1977 film by Robert Aldrich For similarly named articles, see Twilight's Last Gleaming (disambiguation). Twilight's Last GleamingDirected byRobert AldrichScreenplay byRonald M. CohenEdward HuebschBased onViper Three1971 novelby Walter WagerProduced byMerv AdelsonStarringBurt LancasterRoscoe Lee BrowneJoseph CottenMelvyn DouglasCharles DurningRichard JaeckelWilliam MarshallGerald S. O'LoughlinRichard WidmarkPaul WinfieldBurt YoungCinematographyRobert B. HauserEdited byMichael LucianoWilliam Ma...

2015 Filipino filmThe PrenupTheatrical release posterDirected byJun Robles LanaScreenplay byJun Robles LanaDenoy Navarro-PunioProduced byLily Y. MonteverdeRoselle Y. MonteverdeStarringJennylyn MercadoSam MilbyCinematographyCarlo MendozaEdited byVito CajiliMusic byEmerzon TexonProductioncompaniesRegal EntertainmentRegal Multimedia, Inc.Distributed byRegal EntertainmentRelease date October 14, 2015 (2015-10-14) Running time118 minutesCountryPhilippinesLanguagesFilipinoEnglishBox ...

Piano di SorrentoKomuneComune di Piano di SorrentoLokasi Piano di Sorrento di Provinsi NapoliNegara ItaliaWilayah CampaniaProvinsiNapoli (NA)Luas[1] • Total7,34 km2 (2,83 sq mi)Ketinggian[2]96 m (315 ft)Populasi (2016)[3] • Total12.991 • Kepadatan1,800/km2 (4,600/sq mi)Zona waktuUTC+1 (CET) • Musim panas (DST)UTC+2 (CEST)Kode pos80063Kode area telepon081Situs webhttp://www.comune.pi...

National public aviation university in Deyang, Sichuan, China Not to be confused with Civil Aviation University of China. Civil Aviation Flight University of China中国民用航空飞行学院MottoLofty Aspiration, Far-reaching Flight, Profound Knowledge and Great PerseveranceTypeNationalEstablishedMay 26, 1956PresidentGuan Lixin (关立欣)Academic staff800Administrative staff1800Students16000LocationGuanghan, Sichuan, ChinaCampus10.66 square kilometers (2636 acres)Colorsblue, white and red...

Since Iowa became a U.S. state in 1846, it has sent congressional delegations to the United States Senate and United States House of Representatives. Each state elects two senators to serve for six years, and members of the House to two-year terms. Before becoming a state, the Iowa Territory elected a non-voting delegate at-large to Congress from 1838 to 1846. These are tables of congressional delegations from Iowa to the United States Senate and the United States House of Representatives. ...

جزء من سلسلة مقالات حولسياسة المخطط  [لغات أخرى]‏ الفهرس  [لغات أخرى]‏ التصنيف المواضيع الرئيسية اقتصاد سياسي تاريخ سياسي التاريخ السياسي للعالم فلسفة سياسية الأنظمة السياسية لا سلطة دولة مدينة ديمقراطية ديكتاتورية نظام إداري  [لغات أخرى]‏ فدرالية �...

Railway society established in 1999 Waitara Railway Preservation SocietyLocaleWaitara, Taranaki  New ZealandTerminusWaitaraCommercial operationsNameWaitara BranchBuilt byNew Zealand Government RailwaysOriginal gauge1067 mmPreserved operationsOwned byWaitara Railway Preservation SocietyOperated byWaitara Railway Preservation SocietyStationsTwoLength7.45kmPreserved gauge1067 mmCommercial historyOpened1875Closed to passengers1948Closed1999Preservation history1999Purchased from Tranz Rail200...

1934 film by Richard Wallace The Little MinisterTheatrical release posterDirected byRichard WallaceWritten byJane MurfinSarah Y. MasonVictor HeermanBased onThe Little Minister1891 novel and playby J. M. BarrieProduced byPandro S. BermanStarringKatharine HepburnCinematographyHenry W. GerrardEdited byWilliam HamiltonMusic byMax SteinerDistributed byRKO Radio PicturesRelease dateDecember 28, 1934 (1934-12-28)Running time110 minutesCountryUnited StatesLanguageEnglishBudget$648,000&...

Shana LutkerShana Lutker speaking at the Hirshhorn, January 2016Born1978 (age 44–45)NationalityAmericanWebsitewww.shanalutker.com/ Shana Lutker is an artist currently working and living in Los Angeles, CA. Lutker works in sculpture, installation, performance, and text. Her concepts are often synthesized from historical and theoretical research. Lutker is represented in Los Angeles by Susanne Vielmetter Los Angeles Projects. In addition to solo exhibitions at Vielmetter, LAXART,[...

Mascot of the United States Post Office Department Mr. ZIP. Mr. ZIP, informally Zippy, is a cartoon character used in the 1960s by the United States Post Office Department, and later by its successor, the United States Postal Service, to encourage the general public to include the ZIP Code in all mailings. Origins Mr. ZIP on a 1963 sign. The USPS has described the origin of Mr. ZIP as follows:[1][2][3] Mr. ZIP was based on an original design by Howard Wilcox, son of a ...

This article is rated Stub-class on Wikipedia's content assessment scale.It is of interest to the following WikiProjects:Songs This article is within the scope of WikiProject Songs, a collaborative effort to improve the coverage of songs on Wikipedia. If you would like to participate, please visit the project page, where you can join the discussion and see a list of open tasks.SongsWikipedia:WikiProject SongsTemplate:WikiProject Songssong articlesThis article has been automatically rated by a...